Allais’ Manifest
Reality is wonderfully ambitious, and in my view there isn’t any comparably
comprehensive interpretation of Kant’s transcendental idealism that is more
successful. Debate about Kant will be much the better for it.
I think of the book as aiming to resolve two distinct but
linked problems. A first problem focuses on Kant’s notion of appearances, as
distinct from things in themselves. Kant, of course, claims that appearances are
transcendentally ideal and yet empirically real. The problem is to make sense at
once of texts that seem to push toward a mind-dependence of appearances, and
toward a mind-independence of appearances. Second, there is a problem more
focused on things in themselves: Kant argues that we are unavoidably ignorant of
things in themselves; it can be hard to see why this should not block Kant’s own
seeming assertion that there must be things in themselves. Some would defend
extreme solutions, giving up on the face value of the texts on one side or the
other. For example, some would deny that appearances are mind-dependent in any
sense, or that Kant is an idealist in this sense.[2]
In all cases, Allais seeks what she calls a “moderate” interpretation, showing
that she can navigate between the extremes, doing justice to the face value of
texts that initially seem to conflict. Pulling this off with respect to either
problem is difficult; coming up with a joint solution of both seems to me
exponentially more so. And that is the great ambition of
Manifest Reality.
With respect to the first problem, the short story of
Allais’ reading is this: where Kant says that we can cognize only appearances,
he is referring to essentially manifest
features of objects.[3]
This limits us to what are, in a sense, “mind-dependent” properties; but it
“allows that the direct objects of perception are objects in space, not
constructions out of merely mental states” (2015, 135). I find this approach
extremely powerful.
With respect to the other problem, more focused on things
in themselves, matters are different. Here Allais sees, as one extreme,
deflationary readings that would exclude two metaphysical commitments:
1.
There are things in themselves.
2.
Things in themselves stand to appearances in a
relation of metaphysical grounding.
I will note a sense in which the idea of Kant as concerned
with metaphysical grounding might lead us astray, but I do not think that it
need mislead; I agree with Allais that, other things equal, an ideal
interpretation of transcendental idealism will be better if it can find a way to
include some version of these claims.
The other extreme, in Allais’ view, would be a
“noumenalist” reading, according to which Kant would be more specifically
“committed to the existence of non-sensible, non-spatio-temporal entities which
are distinct from the objects of our knowledge… intelligibilia” (2015, 10). I
will defend a broader understanding of the extreme to be avoided, but I agree at
least that noumenalism is among the views that the
Critique does not endorse.
How does Allais navigate between those extremes? With an
interpretation that is metaphysical and also more “two-aspect” rather than
noumanalism’s “two worlds” or “two objects”. Different versions of this approach
will look to texts distinguishing the “outer” from the “inner” or “in itself” of
things, and I will here reserve the terms “inner” and “outer” as neutral between
such interpretations. One specific version would be Langton’s, on which this
distinction is between “intrinsic” and “extrinsic” properties, where “intrinsic”
properties are those compatible with loneliness. But Allais gives a different
account, and one that is remarkable because (in part) of the way it fits her
powerful and balanced approach to the first problem, above. The idea is this:
Kant’s limitation of our cognition to appearances refers, again, to the
essentially manifest features of things. These are
relational properties: those whose
essence involves relations with others.[4]
Allais includes dispositions and powers as helpful cases of relational
properties in this sense; and in this vein she calls the contrasting inner
properties “categorical” as well as “non-relational”.[5]
Further, Allais’ Kant thinks that “there must be something non-relational which
grounds relational appearances” (2015, 18). This construal of the assertion that
there are things in themselves is supposed to be consistent with our ignorance:
we know that there are further properties, but not what they are. There is an
“unknown ground”; “Kant has a metaphysical commitment to an unknown reality
which grounds the world we experience”.[6]
Grounding, here, is an explanatory relation: the categorical properties of
something are responsible for its having the powers and dispositions that it has
(2015, 254).
But while there may be much right in this general
orientation, I think there is a problem, and that the details cannot really get
Kant right. Noumenalist readings are too extreme, specifically because “Kant
clearly argues that … we do not have knowledge such objects exist” (Allais 2015,
61). I agree, and find this central to Kant’s very idea of a critique of reason.
The problem is that what the Critique
says by way of a critique of reason—the topic of the “Transcendental
Dialectic”—does not specifically target “noumenalist” metaphysics. It targets
all metaphysics involving claims supported by a supposed need for “the
unconditioned”. And Allais’ metaphysics of categorical grounds fits precisely
the general kind of view targeted by Kant’s critique. Perhaps the many other
advantages of Allais’ approach could be retained in combination with a new
solution. But the metaphysics described by Allais cannot, I think, be precisely
the view of the Critique. Or so I
argue.
I begin by noting some broadly familiar features of Kant’s
account of the faculty of reason, in the Transcendental Dialectic, borrowing
from Allais’ own interpretation. To begin with, the faculty of reason is
characterized by an interest, or an aim: “For everything caused, contingent, or
not entirely self-explanatory, reason seeks for an explanation, ground, or
cause”. Ultimately, reason seeks a ground that is complete, or “something
unconditioned, something with respect to which no further explanation or ground
could be asked for”. Kant strikes a balance: On the one hand, reason’s interest
“drives science”, and “without this we would not have a coherent use of reason”.
On the other hand, this makes us subject to an illusion:
…we mistake the (unavoidable) principle which tells us to
seek for the conditions for … the
claim that there is a condition...
...natural and unavoidable dissatisfaction with explanatory
incompleteness misleads us into thinking that we have insight into the existence
of the unconditioned…
The illusion in the sense of a temptation toward certain
conclusions stems directly from reason’s interest and is supposed to be natural
and ineliminable; the Critique seeks
to teach us—even while still guided by reason’s demand for the unconditioned—to
“avoid making the erroneous conclusions” (Allais 2015, 90).
Now consider the forms that these erroneous conclusions can
take. There are supposed to be three kinds of “ideas of reason”—psychological,
cosmological, and the theological idea of God. I focus especially on the
Antinomy, concerning the cosmological case, because of its unusual form of
argument. Here reason supports conflicting conclusions, by means of arguments
with one and the same form:
The entire antinomy of pure reason rests on this dialectical
argument: If the conditioned is given, then the whole series of all conditions
for it is also given; now objects of the senses are given as conditioned;
consequently, etc.
The major premise is a version of the deceived principle of
reason, demanding conditions and completeness; thus the “major premise seems so
natural and evident” (A497/B525).
To take one example, the Second Antinomy concerns the
regress from wholes to parts. We can think of this in terms of the image of the
earth resting on a stack of turtles, with turtles all the way down. The
Antithesis argues that the regress to parts must be turtles all the way down, or
specifically composition all the way
down: “[n]o composite thing in the world consists of simple parts” (A435/B463).
The Thesis argues that this regress must have a last turtle: “[e]very composite
substance in the world consists of simple parts” (A434/B462). In the case of the
first two, or “mathematical” antinomies, Kant will try to argue that such
arguments bring us to contradictions. Resolving the contradictions is supposed
to require finding a sense in which both sides are false, requiring in turn
transcendental idealism (A507/B535).
The last two, or “dynamical”, antinomies allow
consideration of an additional scenario, on which there is a ground “different
in kind … outside the series” (A530/B558). For example, in the fourth antinomy
considers the possibility of a necessary being grounding from outside the
regress of contingency (whether it is infinite or not). This ground would be
different in kind, in a respect that does not allow the same question about
conditions to arise again: a necessary being does not raise the question of what
it is contingent on. Instead of last turtle, this is more like a turtle with a
jetpack. Such conceptions are of course a familiar in rationalist metaphysics.
And this should be no surprise: metaphysical
rationalism is a paradigmatic case of
the forms of metaphysics which Kant takes to make a critique of
reason necessary. I have argued that
the deceived way of using the principle of reason, described by Kant, is simply
arguing from the unrestricted principle of sufficient reason, so central to
rationalist metaphysics; the idea is that, “for anything that is not a
sufficient reason for itself, or for anything conditioned, there must be a
complete series of conditions that provides for it a sufficient reason” (Kreines
2008, 49). Kant allows theoretical reasoning from something like this principle
only in the case restricted to time (e.g. A201/B246).[7]
In the dynamical antinomies, Kant is not ruling out either
side (A532/B560). Still, the point—applied to the necessary being—is that, if we
could have legitimate theoretical justification for its existence, then the “the
same ground of proof” would “prove its nonexistence, and indeed with equal
rigor” (A459/B487). So for a theoretical philosophy to assert one side of such
an antinomy would be unacceptable, or one form of “dogmatic stubbornness,
setting its mind rigidly to certain assertions without giving a fair hearing to
the grounds for the opposite” (A407/B434).[8]
With this account of Kant’s critique of reason in hand,
consider again Allais’ account of things in themselves. First, I think it is
clear that the issues Allais highlights, about relational properties like
dispositions, concern a case of what Kant calls
a regress of conditions. For example,
salt has the disposition to dissolve in water. Is this itself brute, or a last
turtle? No. It depends on the properties and arrangement of the underlying
electrons and protons. And so we have our characteristic question about which
pattern the regress fits. Can there be a last turtle, or a brute disposition,
such as a brute dormitive virtue? If we make the deceived use of reason’s
demand, or “the claim that there is a
condition” (Allais 2015, 90), then we will conclude that there cannot be brute
dispositions. Could the regress be only dispositional or relational
all the way down? Allais’ crucial
claim answers directly: “there cannot be relations all the way down; there must
ultimately be intrinsic natures which ground powers” (2015, 255). The
“ultimately” asserts that “all the way down” scenarios lack
completeness of grounding. I think
that similar formulations can be found in general where philosophers see reason
for demanding categorical grounds.[9]
Compare the Thesis of the second Antinomy: if there were only composition, all
the way down, we could consider all of that composition together, and then there
would be nothing left to enter into relations of composition; so there must
ultimately be non-composed grounds of composition.
Granted, the position of the
Critique is that the nature of reason
itself makes this kind of reasoning attractive and commonsensical, and even
nearly irresistible. But this is bad news, at least when it comes to Kant
interpretation. For what explains the appeal of the conclusion Allais sees in
Kant would be the deceived use of reason’s demand for completeness of
conditions—the use against which Kant is warning us. Or it would be another
instance of the argument schema driving the antinomies: there must be
completeness in a regress for something conditioned; relational properties are
conditioned; and so on. Further, this seems to me like this would be clear to
Kant, given that he is so taken with the idea of a critique of reason that he
uses this idea to frame the entire book. So it seems to me that this is a
powerful reason against reading the
Critique as advancing the account of things in themselves that Allais sees
there.
Another way to make the same point is this: while we can
indeed give an intuitively compelling thesis-style argument for the existence of
categorical grounds, the same principle could offer support for an
antithesis-style denial of existence. Compare the antithesis of the fourth
antinomy: On the one hand, a necessary being as ground cannot be either a member
of a regress of contingent alterations, or the sum of all members of this; in
either case, it would be merely contingent.[10]
On the other hand, a necessary being cannot ground a series of contingent
alterations from outside of the series and time; for then it would be outside of
time, and the final ground of the alteration would leave unexplained why it
happens at a particular time[11];
deceived use of reason’s demand for completeness of grounds rules this out. So
with respect to the idea of a necessary being grounding contingent alterations,
this would either not be necessary, or it would not be the ground.
Parallel reasoning applies to any proposed categorical
ground (CG) for a disposition (D): On the one hand, it cannot be in virtue of
the very nature or essence of CG that an object having the property CG must also
have the property D; for then CG would be relational, not categorical. On the
other hand, if the nature of CG is such that it does not require D, in that way,
then CG would not completely explain
why the object possesses D. Anyone willing to reason from a demand for
completeness would then have to deny that CG could really be the ground of D. So
either the categorical ground is not categorical, or it is not the ground.[12]
Allais reads Kant as holding that there must
be categorical grounds, and then
adding that our epistemic limits leave us unable to “understand how they ground
appearances, or even what kind of relation this grounding might be” (2015, 231).
I think that this kind of position is common for rationalists, like Leibniz:
there must be sufficient reasons “although these reasons usually cannot be known
by us” (Monadology #32). I certainly grant that one can formulate an internally
consistent position here; my worries
concern possible reasons for it. First, as a philosophical matter, Kant’s
worries about Antinomy style reasoning seem to me powerful when applied to
categorical grounds: theoretical philosophy can give a case in favor of
existence, but it will rest, whether explicitly or not, on a demand for
completeness; the same demand can equally well support a case for “nonexistence,
and indeed with equal rigor” (A459/B487). So it seems that it would indeed be an
unacceptable form of dogmatic stubbornness for theoretical philosophy to side
with the thesis in asserting existence and then saying that the antithesis fails
to prove non-existence but only limits our understanding. Another way to put the
point: precisely if our understanding of the relevant grounding relation is so
tenuous, we cannot know that an infinite descent of powers or relational grounds
is insufficient to offer completeness of such grounding. Second, as an
interpretive manner, whatever we think of them, these worries about the kind of
reasoning Allais uses are certainly Kant’s worries.
Objection: The
point of the Critique is not entirely
negative, nor entirely about epistemic limits. It includes a metaphysical
assertion that there are things in themselves. In fact, it includes the
metaphysical assertion that there must be “inner” grounds of the “outer”
properties of objects known to us. And even the Antinomy itself is supposed to
justify this metaphysics. Further, Kant’s complex epistemic claims about the
limits of different epistemic states—Erkenntnis,
Wissen, etc.—can be read in
accordance with those assertions.[13]
Reply: I deny
none of this. My point is that there is a powerful reason to deny that “things
in themselves”, in such assertions, could refer to unconditioned grounds,[14]
and so specifically to non-relational or
categorical grounds.[15]
And I did not reason from any claims about epistemic limits; the point of the
Dialectic is to show that our direct pursuit of metaphysics
conflicts with itself;[16]
whatever the complex details about different epistemic states, they are meant in
part to serve the aim of resolving the Dialectic problem about the
unconditioned.
Objection: The
alternative to categorical grounds would be what Allais calls an “entirely
relational ontology”[17],
which Allais shows is not an “intuitive” view (34). The argument above succeeds
at justifying neither that rival ontology, nor the attribution of it to Kant.
Reply: This
objection to my case would misconstrue the options. On my account, the Dialectic
shows that theoretical philosophy should
withhold assertion of either existence or non-existence—of unconditioned
grounds in general, and so categorical grounds in particular.
Objection:
Allais argues that Kant “simply assume”[s] non-relational natures as an
“intuitive starting point”, so her Kant cannot be making the mistake of
arguing on grounds of anything like a
deceived use of reason, because he is not arguing at all.[18]
Reply: First, it
is crucial to Kant’s idea of a critique of reason, from the first words of the
A-preface, that it will target views that
are intuitive, for example in the sense of being “common sense” (Aviii).
Second, it will target presuppositions.
For example, there is a “deception” that is “not artificial, but an entirely
natural mistake of common reason… we presuppose … the conditions and their
series as it were sight unseen”
(A500/B528). Here is another way to think about this: Imagine you assumed that
there are non-relational natures of things, but then realized that we would be
unavoidably ignorant of them. You might still hold on to that existence claim,
or you might give it up. But either way, one can ask
why?[19]
Allais’s Kant holds on to existence,
and has a reason why: “we cannot have a complete ontology with relations
only” (226). On my view, Kant aims to convince theoretical philosophy to give up
views resting on that intuitive assumption about completeness.
Objection: Kant
himself does not apply his critique of reason specifically to the topic of
inner, non-relational properties; thus it is no reason to doubt Allais’ reading.
Reply: I do not
accept the premise. But since interpretation of texts bearing on the matter,
like the Amphiboly discussions of inner properties noted below, would be
controversial, it is important to see that the conclusion would not follow from
the premise anyway. The Critique is a
book that argues, and arguments bring
their own level of generality. Kant argues that it is the faculty of reason that
can lead us astray, and into metaphysical error—and that it can do so because of
principles Kant himself formulates very generally in terms of the notions of
conditions and
the unconditioned. I agree with
Allais interpretation of these notions, cited above, in terms of connections to
the notion of explanation and complete explanation. What follows from Kant’s
argument, then (if successful at all) is that theoretical philosophy should in
general resist assertions whose appeal rests on such a deceived principle
demanding unconditioned grounds. Given the argument as written, and highlighted
by the title of the book, the relevant question is whether Allais’ assertion
(that there are categorical grounds) would be one whose appeal rests on that
kind of principle of reason demanding completeness in a regress of conditions. I
have argued that it is.
Objection:
Kant’s Dialectic criticizes only theories positing distinct, unknowable
objects; the posit of unknowable
properties is exempt because it is
“not making new, unjustified existential commitments” (Allais 2010, 15).
Reply: Allais
thinks that deflationary readings cannot adequately capture the face value of
the texts where Kant asserts that there
are things in themselves; she does better by construing these texts in terms
of the claim that there are additional
non-relational properties of things,
over and above the essentially
manifest properties; so I think she needs this to be
precisely a “new … existential commitment”. I cede that it is not
“unjustified”, but its justification takes precisely the general form targeted
by Kant’s critique of reason. Again, as above, Kant’s own argument concerns
general principles about the unconditioned; there is no limitation to cases of
objects in any sense opposed to properties.
Objection:
Allais argues that the “Amphiboly” of the
Critique asserts the existence of non-relational properties.
Reply: There is
an approach to the Amphiboly that does at least as well the text of that
section—I would think better—and in any case much better with respect to
coherence with the Dialectic. First, Allais holds that “intelligibilia” are
objects “about whose existence Kant is agnostic” (2015, 234). In the Amphiboly,
Kant reconstructs Leibnizian arguments for monads. Allais thinks that Kant
accepts these arguments up to the point of positing that there must be
non-relational properties of things, but then rejects the jump to there being
“monads (things with only inner natures, things that are not spatial)” (235).
But the text of Kant’s reconstructions generally begin by asking us to consider
the notion of “an object of the pure understanding”; or thinking things “merely
in relation to the understanding” or “[a]ccording to mere concepts”.[20]
It is at least as natural, then, to take all of the steps following to follow
only specifically or objects of the pure understanding, or objects given
independently of all sensible intuition—or intelligibilia. The
Critique’s
own view, then, would be—now in accordance with precisely what is required
by the Dialectic—that intelligibilia would need categorical grounds, but that
theoretical philosophy should neither assert nor deny existence of such.[21]
Objection: Some
would argue that the resolution of the Antinomies asserts that the principle
demanding the unconditioned is deceived only when applied to appearances, but
does apply to things in themselves, thus guaranteeing unconditioned grounds
there.[22]
Kant says, for example:
If the conditioned as well as its conditions are things in
themselves, then when the first is given … the latter is thereby already
given
along with it.
(A498/B526; Allais 92)
Reply: On that
proposed reading, the Critique would
clearly have to endorse a thesis argument to an unconditioned necessary being:
appearances require grounding in things in themselves; these things in
themselves could not all be contingent beings, because then reason’s demand,
applied to things in themselves as this reading requires, would allow us to
bundle all contingent things in
themselves and require a further ground for them, and so a necessary being. But,
as above, there is a reading that does better with respect to the stated aims of
the antinomy, withholding assertion from that thesis argument, while doing
better with the text of that passage. The passage above considers what would
follow if a thing in itself “is
given”. The givenness in question would have to be independent of all sensible
intuition, so these would be intelligibilia. Thus the passage says that the
principle in question would require
unconditioned grounds for intelligibilia—about which the
Critique neither asserts nor denies
existence. And that is precisely the view that would be consistent with the
stated aims of the Antinomy: the aim of showing that “it lies beyond our reason
to settle” (A481/B509) such questions about whether there exist unconditioned
grounds, or that it would be “dogmatic stubbornness” for theoretical philosophy
to side with thesis over antithesis here, and so on.
One might worry that my criticism cuts off all hope of
claiming the other considerable advantages of Allais’ approach, including those
concerning appearances; thus (one might argue) it would be worth paying any
costs stemming from the conflict I note with the Dialectic. To defend my
criticism, then, I need to show that there is at least hope of taking the
criticism to heart while retaining the other advantages of Allais’ approach.
Note first that there can seem to be two different notions
of things in themselves at work in Allais:
*
TII-broad: “there
actually is a way things are in themselves
… there exists an aspect of reality that is independent of us.” (2015,
27)
*
TII-narrow: “things have a way that they are independent of their relations
to other things, including us” (2015, 34)
Allais’ precise position is as follows. First, “Kant primarily
uses” the broad notion. But, second, “Kant’s reasons for thinking that there
must be a way things are as they are in themselves” latch onto the narrow sense:
“things must have intrinsic, non-relational natures”; this
allows that there
might also things that fall in the
broad space but not the narrow, or
“relations between them as they are in themselves” (2015, 233).
Here is yet another difficulty for Allais here: she seeks
to distance herself from readings which can seem out of keeping with the face
value of many texts, insofar as ignorance of things in themselves would follow
merely from the fact that our knowledge is receptive, bypassing with what
Ameriks calls a “short argument” all the specifics concerning space and time
being the pure forms of our sensibility. Allais affirms Ameriks’ point (2015,
291). I agree. But on Allais’ just-noted account, Kant’s “reasons” for asserting
existence are reasons for asserting existence specifically of properties that
involve no relations to anything; if
a short argument from receptivity alone demonstrates ignorance, then it would
demonstrate ignorance of things in themselves in precisely this sense.
The fix to all the above would be a reading putting more
emphasis on Allais’ own broad and so less demanding sense. Here is the idea: We
can know how some powers are grounded by comparatively more inner properties,[23]
in the form of other powers. We today might think in terms of the idea that what
is responsible for the power of water to dissolve salt is the power of the
underlying electrons and protons to attract and repel. The Kantian position—here
following Allais’ powerful account of appearances—would be that all these
knowable powers are properties that essentially involve relations to epistemic
subjects of our kind, dependent on sensible intuition, with the
a priori forms of space and time. But
the metaphysical assertion in the
Critique, that there are things in themselves, would then mean this: the
regress of powers extends to properties that ground the knowable properties,
more inner properties of things, unknown to us. As Kant says, appearances “must
have grounds that are not appearances” (A537/B565). What we would know about
these is that they involve no essential relations to epistemic subjects of our
kind—although they may well (for all we can know) be further powers, and so
relational in other respects. For this reason, we cannot know what these further
properties are. What the Critique
would not assert, then, would be any
commitment about how or whether that regress of powers might end, or any
commitment between these options:
1.
Perhaps the regress of powers ends with an
unknowable brute power.
2.
Perhaps there is an infinite regress of powers
all the way down, or (better) all the way
in.
3.
Perhaps the regress comes to categorical grounds,
which in some manner beyond our comprehension more completely ground everything
resting on them.
Thus the Critique
would make the metaphysical assertion about grounds. But this would include no
assertion or denial of the existence of unconditioned grounds, and so no
conflict with the Dialectic. And, further, there would be no assertion of
existence of anything for which our ignorance would follow from a short argument
concerning merely receptivity, if at all.
But I don’t think that Allais could simply amend her view,
in this way; what would be needed is a wholesale replacement for Allais’ account
of Kant’s reasons for the assertion
that there are things in themselves, which (as is) latch onto the narrow notion.
And the replacement reasons will have to be radically different. To see why,
consider this attempt at a slight alteration, arguing from this seemingly
modest principle: where something
stands in a relation to X, this must also have as a ground a property that is
not a relation to X. Given appearances as essentially involving relations
to us, it would follow immediately
that there must be properties that are essentially independent
of us (even if not independent of all
relations)—just the modest claim we seek. But that principle would also push us
back into antinomy arguments, by means of the bundling step central in a
cosmological argument, or the thesis of the second antinomy: just take
all the relational properties of an
object, and make out of them a conjunctive super-property, P; since we have
bundled all the relational features
together, it would now still follow from the modest principle that objects must
specifically have properties that do not essentially involve relations
to anything: categorical grounds—just
the dogmatic assertion we seek to avoid. As far as I can see, the problem will
equally affect other attempts, whether two-aspect or two-world, to find reasons
that extend from the known, by intuitive principles requiring grounds, to the
existence of things in themselves.[24]
I think that Kant provides the needed and radically
different form of reasoning in the Antinomy. Here the argument does not begin
with the known and attempt to expand by intuitive principles about grounds. It
is more the reverse, or more that the argument experimentally makes very
extensive knowledge claims—insofar as it considers the possibility that
appearances are things in themselves, it considers
everything as continuous with the
knowable. It then demonstrates that contradictions follow. For we must always at
least think the unconditioned,
insofar as we must, as rational, always be guided by regulative principles
demanding that we seek the unconditioned; perhaps, as Kant often suggests, such
guidance requires us to presuppose for
the sake of inquiry that there are unconditioned grounds.[25]
And yet the thought or presupposition would generate the contradictions of the
first two antinomies. Resolving the contradictions is supposed to require
transcendental idealism, which the Antinomy is thus “proving indirectly”
(A506/B534). And transcendental idealism, on the face of it, means rolling back
the extent of our knowledge in a very distinctive manner, precluding knowledge
of things in themselves, but leaving knowledge that there are things in
themselves grounding appearances. Kant sketches the relevant argument in
glossing the overall case of the Critique
in the B-Preface:
…if we find that on the assumption that our cognition from
experience conforms to the objects as things in themselves, the unconditioned
cannot be thought at all without
contradiction … if we assume that our representation of things as they are
given to us does not conform to these things as they are in themselves… then
the contradiction disappears…
(Bxx-xxi)
On this reading, the point of the metaphysical assertion that
there are things in themselves does have to do with ideas of unconditioned
grounds; but that assertion does not assert the existence of unconditioned
grounds; the point is to save room for thoughts or presuppositions about, or
belief in, some forms of them.[26]
Needless to say, much more would need to be done to develop
such an interpretive approach. My point here has not been to completely develop
or defend this, but to deal with the objection that my criticism would leave no
hope for claiming the otherwise considerable advantages of Allais’ interpretive
approach.
Finally, I should concede that I have here been thinking
about the Critique of Pure Reason in
a manner that may be unfamiliar.
Perhaps some will think that my evidence here, concerning the idea of a natural
illusion, must carry much less weight than consideration of other aims. For
instance, some would introduce the
Critique in terms of a familiar anti-skeptical aim. Perhaps some today would
introduce it as aiming to construct a metaphysics of grounding. I do not deny
that something like these aims is present in the
Critique. But I emphasize that there
is also an organizing frame that Kant
himself uses to integrate together the book’s many aims. That frame concerns
the critique of reason announced by the title, and this should impact our
interpretations.[27]
So the idea that Kant aims to construct a metaphysics of grounding
could lead us astray. It will mislead
if we think, in terms that come so naturally to us, of an ambition to construct
a complete metaphysics of
grounding—and if we then set about supplying Kant with the resources we would
need to that end. This is yet another juncture at which I find Allais’ counsel
of moderation so important, even if I would follow it in a slightly different
direction. For while Kant does argue that reason itself is always concerned with
metaphysical grounds, and ultimately with complete, fundamental grounds, we
should understand Kant’s ambitions concerning this topic first of all in terms
of the idea of a critique—or the idea
that the most natural ways of pursuing a complete metaphysics of grounding will
always generate antinomy contradictions or the other problems discussed in
Kant’s Dialectic. Kant’s antidote might well include some more modest claims
about metaphysical grounding, carefully tailored to resolve the contradictions,
blocking rather than satisfying our natural ambitions to completeness. This
critical aim of using metaphysics against itself, or to limit itself, is no
doubt today less familiar. But, first, this should make it all the more
interesting: it provides us the occasion to consider Kant’s
arguments in favor of pursuing
philosophy differently. And, second, regardless of our orthodoxies, thinking
first of all in in terms of an antinomy and an illusion itself is essential to
Kant’s organizing frame for the
Critique of Pure Reason.
I conclude, then, as follows: There is no comparatively
comprehensive interpretation of transcendental idealism that is, in my view,
more successful than Allais’ ambitious
Manifest Reality. With respect to Kant on things in themselves, however, I
think Allais’ account retains one disadvantage common to its competitors.
Escape, as I see it, requires different understanding of the extremes that a
“moderate” interpretation should avoid: On the one extreme, there are indeed
deflationary readings, precluding a metaphysical assertion of the existence of
things in themselves as grounds of appearances. But the other extreme is not
precisely noumenalism, as Allais claims, but
any metaphysics asserting the
existence of unconditioned grounds, or metaphysical fundamentality in this
sense; the argument of the Dialectic rules these all to be unacceptably
dogmatic, and for what seem to me powerfully philosophical reasons. I would
think that the big interpretive challenge is to navigate between these extremes
concerning things in themselves—hopefully in a manner that can retain access to
the many unmatched advantages of Allais’ interpretation of Kant on appearances.
[1] For comments, feedback,
and help with these issues, I thank Lucy Allais, Caroline Bowman, Tobias
Rosefeldt, Nick Stang, and the students in my Fall 2015 seminar on Kant
and Transcendental Idealism.
[2] Abela (2002) and Langton
(1998) are (although otherwise very different) two of Allais’ examples
of non-idealist readings, in this sense (Allais 2015, 4).
[3] As Allais notes, others
have been working in a comparable direction, with her position falling
closest to Rosefeldt (2007).
[4] Actual or possible
relations, I would think. Compare Wedgwood (1997) on response-dependence
more specifically, and Langton’s reply to Allais (2006, 174n6).
[5] “[L]ike dispositional
properties, perceptual appearing is essentially relational” (123)
[6] Respectively, A380 cited
by Allais (2015, 32, 245, 257), and then (2015, 95). Allais refers to
“unknowability”; I think this is right. It may be that this unknowbility
derives from a more basic epistemic restriction concerning “cognition” (Erkenntnis),
and there may be other such limits as well; but Kant does include a
limit best expressed by saying that we cannot have knowledge of things
in themselves.
[7] See, e.g., UE 8:198 for
Kant’s
rejection of an unrestricted, rationalist PSR.
[8] Obviously, Kant endorses
some epistemic attitudes in relation to some conceptions of the
unconditioned—for example, belief or
Glaube, in an unconditioned
free will (itself the topic of the third antinomy). The endorsed
attitudes may be surprisingly strong. Still, I think Allais and I agree
that the Critique asserts
without such limitation that
there are things in themselves, and that theoretical philosophy
demonstrates this. So even if one could show that Kant advocates some
specific positive epistemic state X with respect to categorical
grounds—this would still not be justification for reading the direct or
non-limited arguments for the existence of things in themselves as
referring to those categorical grounds.
[9] E.g. Blackburn (1990, 64),
Chalmers (1996, 153).
[10] “[T]he existence of a
multiplicity cannot be necessary if no single part of it possesses an
existence necessary in itself” (A453/B481).
[11] “[I]t would have to begin
to act then, and its causality would belong in time” (A453/B481).
[12] I have borrowed
especially from Blackburn’s (1990, 63) version here, and there is
something similar in Langton’s discussion of what she calls “the
contemporary orthodoxy” about qualities (1998, 176).
[13] For the idea that it is
Kant’s metaphysics rather shapes his epistemology, see for example
Heimsoeth, 1924.
[14] I think Ameriks at one
point falls onto the wrong side of this line, in saying that “Kant
states that if transcendental idealism is accepted, then … there must be
some ground for appearances which is itself unconditional” (1981, 58).
He cites Kant: “appearances … must have grounds that are not
appearances” (A537/B565). I will show below that “grounds that are not
appearances” need not be
unconditioned grounds for the relevant regress, even if the point of
asserting the existence of the former is to save room for the thought,
presupposition of, or belief in the latter.
[15] I do think that Kant uses
“inner” to mean something like Allais’ non-relational properties in
those cases where Kant is denying that philosophy can settle whether or
not there is anything absolute “inner” in things; I return to the
Amphiboly, which I take to contain such cases, below.
[16] I pursue this idea and
its advantages for Kant in my (2015).
[17] Allais 2105, 226, 232,
239, and 256.
[18] Allais 2015, 34. As noted
there, this approach stems from Adickes (1924), and has been followed by
Ameriks (2006).
[19] I am here borrowing for
different purposes a strategy employed by Hogan (2009, 509) against
Ameriks.
[20] Respectively A265/B321;
A274/B330; and A282/B338. All cited on Allais 2015, 236-9.
[21] I would respond in this
way to comparable readings of the Amphiboly by
Adams
(1997, 810), Van
Cleve (1988, 236), and Langton (1998, 128-9).
[22] This passage is read in
this way by Adams (1997, 810) and Van Cleve (1999, 292#42). Guyer reads
it in this way as well (1987, 387), but recognizes that it would then
contradict Kant’s critical views; he takes this as a worry about Kant,
but given the availability of the alternative I think it is a strike
against this interpretation.
[23] On the comparatively
inner, see Allais (2015, 224ff.) and the passages cited there, and
Warren 2001, 44ff.
[24] I argue elsewhere (ms)
that same applies to Lantgon’s reading, which (on my account) demands
unconditioned grounds, only now with respect to a different kind of
regress: from the extrinsic to the intrinsic. This is a different kind
of grounding or dependence relation. I would say this: For X to
thin-ground Y is for X to exist in virtue of Y, but without any specific
character of X being in virtue of Y. For X to thick-ground Y is for X to
exist with its specific character in virtue of Y. Allais argues that
relational properties, like powers and dispositions, require thick
grounds: something must have a further property in virtue of which it
has its relational properties, so that the former
explains the latter. Langton
argues that: dispositions and powers do not require thick grounds;
matter could resist penetration entirely in virtue of a power of
impenetrability; extrinsic properties require thin-grounds, or require
for their instantiation that there are independent substances to
instantiate them, which could exist all alone, and thus must have some
or other properties that they would have if existing alone
(1998, 18). For these
reasons, I am skeptical of Allais’ idea that her Kant can also draw
support from principles on which she agrees with Langton, requiring
intrinsic properties (2105, 248). Take the disposition to dissolve in
water. On the face of it, some salt would still be water soluble, even
if there were no water. Langton
has the
philosophically fascinating proposal that Kant allows as intrinsic only
properties compatible with loneliness
and lawlessness, which turn
out to be inert (Langton 1998, 119). But I agree with Allais that there
are interpretive problems preventing attribution of this idea to the
critical Kant (Allais 2015, 345), so I think this line of arguing
promises no help for her reading.
[25] E.g. The “logical maxim”
requiring us to seek the unconditioned “cannot
become a principle of
pure reason
unless we assume that
when the conditioned in given, then so is the whole series of conditions
subordinated one to the other, which is unconditioned, also given (i.e.
contained in the object and its connection)” (A307/B364). On this
connection see especially Grier (2001).
[26] I am much influenced here
by Allison’s idea that Kant’s argument aims to open “conceptual space”,
as he often says, for the unconditioned (e.g. 1990, 44). Also by
Ameriks’ construal of the Antinomy argument (1992, 339). But, contra
Ameriks, I would not see it as an argument from a premise requiring
unconditioned grounds. And, with Ameriks and against Allison, I would
see it as an argument for a metaphysical conclusion.
[27] For example, we should
not say that Kant aims to reject skepticism in favor of common sense; as
Guyer shows, Kant’s position is that our common sense, given reason,
generates contradictions in the Dialectic; and “for Kant dialectic is
one of the chief sources of skepticism” (2003, 4)