Metaphysics without Pre-Critical Monism:
Hegel on Lower-Level Natural Kinds and the Structure of Reality
By
James
Kreines
Please cite
the published version in
the Hegel Society
of Great Britain. What follows is only the final draft:
I. Hegel and Metaphysics
Recent debates about Hegel’s theoretical philosophy are
marked by a surprising lack of agreement, extending all the way down to the
most basic question: what is Hegel
talking about? On the one hand, proponents of ‘metaphysical’
interpretations generally read Hegel as aiming to articulate the overall
structure or organization of reality itself, and the nature of a highest or
most fundamental being. Particularly influential is the idea that Hegel is
reviving and modifying a form of Spinoza’s metaphysical monism, according to
which the organized whole of everything is the highest being, providing a
ground or reason for everything real.
On the other hand, proponents of ‘non-metaphysical’ interpretations argue
Hegel’s topic is something else entirely. The idea is that Hegel agrees with
Kant in finding pre-critical forms of metaphysics to be uncritical or
dogmatic. And the topic of Hegel’s positive project is supposed to be not
the nature of reality itself, nor any most fundamental being, but rather
‘forms of thought’ akin to Kant’s categories and the objectivity,
legitimacy, or normative authority of those forms of thought.
This is of course only a rough sketch of the most basic
recent debate, about which there is more to say than can fit in this paper.
My focus here is on what Hegel has to say about nature and natural kinds, in
‘Observing Reason’ from the
Phenomenology, and also in similar material from the
Logic and
Encyclopedia. I intend to argue
that this material suggests a surprising way of stepping beyond the
fundamental debate sketched above. There can of course be no question of
elaborating and defending here a complete interpretation of Hegel’s entire
theoretical philosophy. I will have to restrict myself to arguing for the
unlikely conclusion that there is an approach that can combine and integrate
the strongest points made by both sides in the most basic debate shaping
recent Hegel interpretation.
In defending such a conclusion, it is necessary to
avoid resting any weight on mere invocation of Hegel’s terminology. At the
end of the day, the basic point must not be that Hegel’s view is
dialectical and thus both
cancels and
preserves metaphysics. For this
alone would not explain anything. What needs explaining is how there could
be any single coherent position that in any philosophical sense both cancels
and preserves metaphysics.
To do better, I first need to define some terms, not in
a manner aimed to mirror Hegel’s own usage, but rather in a manner aimed at
making recent debates and my claims in response to them as clear as
possible. First, by ‘metaphysics’ I mean any claim or theory concerning
reality itself, and especially any claim or theory about a general nature of
reality, general features or structure of reality, or about relations of
dependence and independence among real things.
Second, I want to single out a specific kind of
metaphysics. By ‘metaphysical rationalism’ I mean any view combining these
two features: A commitment to a principle of sufficient reason, requiring
that everything real must depend on some complete underlying ground or
reason, so that there must be a complete explanation for everything. And
also an inference to the conclusion that there must ultimately be some one
fundamental being that grounds or provides the ultimate or complete reason
for absolutely everything.
Metaphysical rationalism is of great importance in
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason.
Kant argues that the faculty of reason always demands that we seek
underlying conditions, and ultimately that we seek a complete series of
conditions, or an unconditioned ground: ‘the proper principle of reason in
general … is to find the unconditioned for conditioned cognitions of the
understanding’ (A307/B364). But Kant argues that we can never achieve
theoretical knowledge of anything unconditioned.
So the faculty of reason demands that we seek knowledge of something of
which we cannot achieve knowledge. This means that reason’s principle must
be restricted to a special status: it is legitimate only as ‘regulative’ or
guiding principle for our theoretical inquiry. But Kant argues that we are
naturally tempted to instead accept it as an objective principle
guaranteeing that, for anything conditioned, there must really
be some complete series of
conditions, or some unconditioned ground.
Our temptation to accept this principle, and conclusions drawn from it, is
supposed to explain the appeal of rationalist metaphysics. For example, this
principle is the ground on which the ‘the entire antinomy of pure reason
rests’: ‘If the conditioned is given, then the whole series of all
conditions for it is also given’ (A497/B525). And this tempting principle is
a version of the principle of sufficient reason: for anything that is not a
sufficient reason for itself, or for anything conditioned, there must be a
complete series of conditions that provides for it a sufficient reason. Kant
can explain in these terms, for example, why we are naturally tempted by
rationalist arguments from the existence of anything conditioned to the
existence of God as an ultimate ground or an original being.
But he can also argue that such rationalist arguments must be rejected: to
assert knowledge of the principle grounding such arguments, or of such
conclusions, is to violate our epistemic limits—for these limits prevent all
knowledge of anything unconditioned.
Now when it comes to Hegel, one can certainly propose
that he assumes the basic premises of metaphysical rationalism, and argues
for a modified version of that kind of view. But one should then accept that
this is to beg the question against Kant—it is to meet with mere assumptions
Kant’s arguments against rationalism. We must not let Hegel off too easily
on this score. We should not say that Kant’s criticisms of rationalist
metaphysics target specifically the idea that that there is a transcendent
or otherworldly God, separate from the world; nor should we say that Hegel
escapes Kant’s criticisms of rationalism insofar as Hegel follows Spinoza in
rejecting such a transcendent God.
For metaphysical rationalism need not have anything to do with anything
otherworldly. Kant himself says that one way to think about the
‘unconditioned’ is to think of it as ‘the whole series, in which thus every
member without exception is conditioned’ (A417/B445). And one could hold
that everything real is part of just such a series, so that everything real
has an unconditioned ground in the whole or totality of reality. This kind
of monism would be a form of metaphysical rationalism; I will call it
‘rationalist monism.’ Interpretation of Spinoza is beyond my scope here, but
it is worth noting some affinities with the ‘rationalist monism’ just
defined: Spinoza argues for the existence of God by appealing to the
principle of sufficient reason: ‘For each thing there must be assigned a
cause, or reason, both for its existence and for its nonexistence’ (Ethics
IP11D); and the God defended by Spinoza is a single substance
encompassing everything: ‘whatever is, is in God’ (Ethics IP15).
In any case, if Hegel accepts
‘rationalist monism,’ then he endorses a form of metaphysical rationalism,
and he cannot also agree with Kant in rejecting metaphysical rationalism as
dogmatic.
I argue that Hegel rejects rationalist monism. And I do
not mean that he somehow rejects that view but also accepts it. We can
rather explain his position clearly and directly: Hegel entirely rejects all
forms of metaphysical rationalism, including rationalist monism. He holds
that there is no single ground providing a complete reason for everything
real, not even in the whole of everything. This is to say that
non-metaphysical interpretations are correct about something important:
Hegel rejects a form of metaphysics that Kant was especially concerned to
criticize.
But I will argue that all this is compatible with recognition that Hegel’s
project remains ambitiously metaphysical: Hegel claims to articulate the
structure or organization of reality, and to identify something that is
supposed to be most fundamental or ‘absolute.’
II. Levels of Being and the Lower-Level Natural Kinds
Hegel argues that there are ‘levels’ of reality, or
levels of being. His account of these levels is not supposed to remain
neutral on metaphysical issues by being limited to an account of a
conceptual scheme or relationships between levels of a conceptual scheme.
Hegel argues that reality itself has the structure of a hierarchy of levels.
For example, Hegel argues that the natural sciences can discover real
natural kinds and laws; the sciences can succeed at ‘finding universal
determinations, kinds [Gattungen],
and laws’ (EL §12An). And at the beginning of the
Philosophy of Nature, Hegel
characterizes the ‘levels’ of nature as an ‘organization’ of ‘orders and
classes’ of ‘forces, laws and kinds’ (PN §246). The lecture notes attached
to this paragraph emphasize that neither these kinds nor their organization
is just an abstraction of ours: the ‘kinds,’ Hegel says, ‘are not just a
grouping of similarities, an abstraction made by us … they are the objects’
own inner essence; the orders not only serve to give us a general view, but
form a hierarchy of nature itself.’ (PN §246Zu 9:20/10)
Some will think that Kant’s epistemic restrictions
should block the possibility of knowledge of such natural laws and kinds. I
argue elsewhere (2007) that Hegel has arguments to offer in response to such
epistemological worries, and that these arguments are compatible with
Hegel’s agreement with Kant in rejecting metaphysical rationalism as
dogmatic. But I focus here on the metaphysical question of whether Hegel’s
account of the levels of reality amounts to a kind of metaphysical
rationalism. I aim to approach this question by considering how the lower
levels of nature are supposed to fit into the overall organization of
everything. The lowest level of nature, ‘mechanism,’ is composed of the
single natural kind matter, and
the laws governing all matter.
I will focus my attention one level higher. Here we find not a single basic
natural kind, like matter, but multiple natural kinds linked by laws. In the
‘Observing Reason’ section of the
Phenomenology, Hegel often uses the example of positive electrical
charge and the laws governing its reactions with negative charge, and the
example of acids, which are disposed to react in various ways with bases. He
also discusses this topic in the
Logic, labeling this broad level of nature ‘Chemism,’ while noting that
the topic of such natural kinds linked by laws is broader than just the
specific subject area of the science of chemistry (WL 6:429/727).
Hegel argues that the very nature of such a natural
kind will depend on its relations to others. What it is to be acidic, for
example, depends on how acids react with bases. There is no part of the
answer to the question ‘what is it to be acidic?’ that is independent of the
laws governing its relations with other kinds. In Hegel’s terms, the general
point is that ‘the chemical object is not comprehensible from itself alone,
and the being of one is the being of the other’ (WL 6:430/728). And this
will mean that the ‘being’ of such a kind will depend on the whole
interconnected network of kinds and laws within which it is a part. In
Hegel’s terms, on this level of nature the ‘determinateness’ of anything in
particular ‘is the concrete moment of the individual concept [Begriff]
of the whole, which Begriff is
the universal essence, the real kind
[Gattung]
of the particular object’ (WL 6:430/728).
Note that Hegel’s point here has not been rendered
outdated by progress in the natural sciences. True, we can today explain the
natures of different chemical kinds in terms of their underlying chemical
structure. But this scientific progress only shifts the domain to which
Hegel’s point would apply; it does not settle the question of whether the
basic point is correct. For chemical structure will have to be a structure
of something. Say for the moment that it is at the basic level the structure
of electrons, protons and neutrons. The question will now be, what is an
electron? One answer will be that an electron is fundamentally something
that interacts in certain law governed ways with other electrons and other
basic particles. To accept that answer is to accept Hegel’s philosophical
point about the lower-level natural kinds and laws.
Whatever natural kinds turn out
to be most basic, so long as there are diverse kinds connected by laws, we
can consider whether Hegel’s philosophical point would apply there.
Some philosophers recently have argued that it must. Consider
Blackburn:
Just as the molecular theory gives us only
things with dispositions, any conceivable improvement in science will give
us only a better pattern of dispositions and powers. That's the way physics
works. Is it the way it has to work? I believe so.
A quick route to this conclusion is to see
the theoretical terms of a science as defined functionally, in terms of
their place in a network of laws. (1990: 63)
This is to say that Hegel’s philosophical conclusion is correct of the
objects of physics, and must be.
But contemporary philosophers generally take this conclusion to raise
a problem. In Armstrong’s terms, the objects of physics:
[S]how a distressing tendency to dissolve
into relations that one object has to another. What, then, are the things
that have these relations to each other? Must they not have a non-relational
nature if they are to sustain relations? (1993: 282)
Chalmers similarly worries that the resulting view of physical reality as
entirely relational would be ‘a strangely insubstantial view of the physical
world’ (1996: 153-154). Bertrand Russell insists that physical reality
cannot be so:
There are many possible ways of turning some
things hitherto regarded as ‘real’ into mere laws concerning the other
things. Obviously there must be a limit to this process, or else all the
things in the world will merely be each other's washing (1954: 325)
Some, including Russell and Chalmers, take seriously the possibility that
this worry might motivate a form of panpsychism, or a similar view: the view
that physical reality has an inner side, as it were, that is at least akin
to the mental or phenomenal—that ‘the intrinsic properties of the physical
are themselves a variety of phenomenal property’ (as Chalmers reads Russell)
or ‘proto-phenomenal properties’ (as Chalmers suggests).
Consideration of the contemporary worry about the
strangely insubstantial view of nature can help us to place Hegel’s view
more precisely. One possibility is that Hegel
agrees with Russell that there
must be something real over and above things that are each other’s washing,
something independent of its relations to other things. Of course, we have
just seen that Hegel denies that individual lower-level natural kinds can be
this independent something. But that leaves open the possibility that Hegel
finds the independent something in
the whole network of laws and kinds. The view would be this: physical
reality consists of basic natural kinds. What it is to be one such kind
would be to be disposed to react in certain ways with others. But the whole
network would have an intrinsic nature, and understanding this nature would
provide an explanation of why there are such kinds, and why they are
interrelated as they are. So the whole would have a nature that itself
determines or provides a reason for all of the parts and the relationships
between them. On such a view, physical reality would not be ‘strangely
insubstantial,’ in Chalmer’s terms; what would be strange would rather be
that all of the substantiality is found only in the whole of physical
reality.
But this sort
of monism is precisely what we do not
find in Hegel’s account of this level of nature. Hegel is rather arguing
that this level of physical reality
is ‘strangely insubstantial.’ There is something missing on this level
of nature—it is marked by a lack of anything independently substantial. For
example, ‘Observing Reason’ says of the relation between acids and bases,
that ‘they are only this relation’ (Phän 3:195/153). And what is crucial is
that even the whole network, on this lower level of nature, is nothing over
and above the relations of its parts; not even the whole has an
independently substantial nature that determines why there are distinct
parts or nodes, and why they are linked in the way that they are. The whole
rather merely presupposes the
differences between and relations among natural kinds. In the terms from the
Logic, chemism ‘has as its
presupposition, not just the differentiated nature of the objects, but also
their immediate independence’ (EL
§202). Similarly, if grasping the whole were to reveal a reason for or
explanation of why the different kinds are related as they are, then this
would be to reveal an intrinsic
or internal connection between
kinds; but Hegel says that, on this level of nature, ‘these forms still
remain external to each other’ (EL §202). The differentiation of separate
kinds is immediate, or has no
mediating ground or
determination—not in the whole or anywhere else: ‘chemism’ is ‘still
infected with the immediate self-subsistence of the object and with
externality’ (WL 6:434/731). Finally, it is not the case that this whole
itself determines the differentiation of and relationships between its
parts—the whole or totality of kinds and laws is
‘not yet’ what
Hegel calls a ‘totality of self-determination’ (WL 6:434/731-2).
So on this level of nature everything is strangely
insubstantial. Hegel does not deny but rather highlights the strangeness. In
‘Observing Reason’ in the
Phenomenology, Hegel expresses the point in this way: we can observe an
instance of some physical kind—some acid, for example—and it certainly seems
independently substantial. But when we seek to
understand what it is we are
observing, we find something confusing: it ‘gets lost’ in its relations with
others, or dissolved into chains of dependence; it ‘becomes something else
than it is empirically, confuses cognition’ (Phän 3:190/149). Note the
similarity to recently prominent discussions: in Armstrong’s terms, for
example, such things ‘show a distressing tendency to dissolve into
relations’ (1993: 282). Hegel’s claim here is not that we find something
substantial in the whole; rather something—independent substantiality—goes
missing entirely. In fact, Hegel refers to this result as a kind of
‘contradiction’ inherent in this level of reality: everything here is
dependent; and yet we cannot understand how anything here could be dependent
because there is nothing here independent enough that anything could depend
upon it. Alternatively: the various natural kinds are merely dependent on
one another within a whole network; but this ‘confuses cognition’ insofar as
nothing, not even the whole network, can provide the sort of independent
support upon which something might depend. Or, finally, the parts depend on
one another within a whole network, so that the concept or ‘Begriff
of the whole’ is ‘the real kind of the particular object’; but this is
confusing insofar as the whole itself merely
presupposes the differentiated
kinds, or depends on their differentiation as a kind of
posit: ‘the chemical object … is
thus the contradiction of its immediate positedness and its immanent
individual concept’ (WL 4:430/728).
III. A Brief Look at the Higher Levels: Biology and Spirit
My focus here is Hegel’s account of the lower level of
physical reality discussed above. But in order to consider how this level
fits into the larger hierarchy, I need to consider as well the higher
levels. What is really important here is that each higher level is supposed
to diminish the lack or absence of independent substantiality that
characterizes the lower levels of nature. Now it might be difficult to see
what this could mean. Or perhaps it seems unintelligible. To answer such
worries, I will very briefly sketch an interpretation of Hegel’s account of
the higher levels. But there can be no question of defending the details of
my interpretation of all this. What is crucial is to develop some terms in
which to discuss the higher levels, so as to then return to consider in a
determinate manner how these relate to the lower levels.
Consider first Hegel’s account of the biological level
of nature. Of course, Hegel is wrong wherever his claims contradict later
scientific insights, such as those in evolutionary biology. But I have
argued elsewhere (2008) that Hegel’s philosophical argument in defense of
teleological explanation in biology is entirely independent of any such
obsolete scientific claims. More specifically, Hegel argues that living
beings are composed of material parts themselves explicable in lower-level
terms—for example, in terms of the natural laws and kinds noted above; and
Hegel provides philosophical arguments for the conclusion that living beings
themselves are not explicable in lower-level terms, but rather in
teleological terms.
Here what is important is the way in which this claim
about teleology relates to the lack of substantiality discussed above.
Recent philosophers tend to worry about the idea that physical reality might
lack purely non-relational properties
to support its relational properties. But Blackburn (1990: 64) points out
that it is hard to even conceive of how there could be such support: to say
that X is an underlying non-relational property that supports relational
properties would be to characterize X in relational terms—in terms of its
grounding or supporting something else. In any case, Hegel conceives of the
lack of substantiality differently: he conceives of it as a lack of any
independent source of activity. So he is especially interested in the sense
in which a living organism does not depend on something else outside of it
to determine its nature; its nature is fixed by the way that it itself
employs the different parts of its body in actively seeking survival. In
‘Observing Reason,’ Hegel says that ‘the distinguishing marks of animals,
e.g., are taken from their claws and teeth … each animal itself
separates itself from others
thereby’ (Phän 3:190/149). The idea is that determinate features such as
claws and teeth, used in determinate ways, fix the nature of a biological
species.
For example, part of what distinguishes a species of tiger is the specific
way in which it uses its claws to climb the trees present in its
environment, to hunt prey present in its environment, etc. Compare this
relation between animal and environment to Hegel’s account of acids and
bases. In the latter case we are supposed to get lost in chains of
dependence: If we ask why an acid behaves in a certain way in the presence
of something basic, we find that it is the nature of an acid to react with a
base in this way. We might seek further explanation by considering the
nature of a base, but we are then led back to acids: we find that it is the
nature of something basic to react with acids in this way. Of course,
current physics can pursue the matter further, but the idea is that we still
come to a point at which we get lost in such chains of dependence. But
matters are different with the tiger and its environment. If we ask why the
tiger has certain features, then—although we will find some limitations here
as well—there is at least an answer that can make more progress toward
explanation by referring to this very kind of thing itself: it has those
features on account of their contribution to an end intrinsic to the tiger,
namely, self-preservation. For example, Hegel says, ‘in this way the living
thing is articulated purposefully; all its members serve only as means to
the one end of self-preservation’ (VPA
13:193/1:145).
So the intrinsic end is supposed to allow the nature of a biological
species-kind to be manifest in the determinate way that it relates to the
environment, yet without its nature being merely dependent on such
relations. In ‘Observing Reason’ Hegel says, for example, that the organism
is ‘the real end or Zweck itself
… it preserves itself in the relation to an other’
(Phän 3:198/156).
As noted above, Hegel takes the natural sciences
generally to seek knowledge of ‘universal determinations, kinds [Gattungen],
and laws’ (EL §12An). But now we can appreciate his reasons for claiming
that there is a philosophically significant difference between two different
orders or classes of natural kinds or
Gattungen: lower level natural kinds connected by laws lack the
independent substantiality of higher level biological species-kinds. This is
the sort of difference in virtue of which Hegel concludes that there are
distinct levels of natural kinds, so that nature itself has an organization
or structure.
Hegel is also interested in biology because he finds
here, for the first time, an explanation of the interdependence of the whole
and of the parts. Reproduction by individuals explains how the general kind
[Gattung] is realized and
effective in the world; and the general kind reciprocally explains the
development and capacities of each new concrete individual. Here concrete
and the universal are supposed to be two sides of one system, which Hegel
calls ‘concrete universality.’
But it is crucial that Hegel will also find a
limitation on this biological level. A biological species-kind has,
at a fixed point in time, the
sort of independent substantiality noted above. But a biological kind itself
is shaped over time by its
environment. Hegel says, in the course of praising Cuvier: ‘nature shapes
and adapts this organism to the particular element in which it is placed, to
climate, to a particular form of food, in general, to the environment’ (PN
§368An). Hegel adds that the biological species-kinds are shaped by
contingent changes in the environment: ‘the kinds
[Gattungen]
are completely subject to the changes of the external, universal life of
nature, the vicissitudes of which are shared by the life of the animal’ (PN
§368An). This is supposed to make biological life, although it is the
highest level of nature, similar to lower levels in that it lacks anything
whose nature is completely
determined in an independent manner. Alternatively, things on this level of
nature are also dependent for their nature on their relations over time with
other merely external parts of the natural environment and biological life
generally.
Although biology is supposed to be the highest level of
nature, there is supposed to be
an additional highest level of being, the level of
Geist or ‘spirit.’
Spirit is something akin to a
biological species-kind or Gattung,
and so a kind of concrete universal. This is to say that spirit and its
distinction from nature has nothing to do with immaterial substance.
Individual geistig beings are
composed of matter, like all living beings.
Geistig beings are distinguished
by the capacities for thought and self-consciousness. And these capacities
are supposed to ground yet another philosophically significant distinction
between classes of kinds—they are supposed to make the general kind
Geist different than a biological
species or lower-level natural kinds.
More specifically, these capacities are supposed to
make Geist change over time in a
unique manner. First, Hegel will argue that spirit
develops or changes over time, through different shapes or structures,
even where there is no change in the natural environment and no change in
the biological structure of individuals. An example of such a change, from
the Phenomenology, would be the
breakdown of ancient Greek ethical life, which Hegel approaches by
considering Sophocles’ Antigone.
Second, the point is not just that spirit is
independent of nature in its development; spirit is supposed to develop in a
manner that depends on itself. For example, Hegel will argue that thinking
and self-conscious beings cannot sustain a form of life in which questions
are answered and conflicts resolved by appeal to tradition or to nature.
Such beings will inevitably come into conflict over questions of who or what
they are, and over what they should do and should become. Further, such
beings will be increasingly aware
that they are shaped by such internal conflicts, more than by any
external factors, such as the natural environment. So, over time, such
beings will be less able to resolve conflicts, and less interested in
resolving conflicts, by appealing to a supposedly given or fixed nature of
things, or to tradition; they are supposed to inevitably tend, over the very
long haul, toward developing ways of legitimately resolving conflicts and
reconciling that are independent of such external appeal. In terms of the
Phenomenology, spirit develops
toward mutual recognition, or toward what Hegel calls ‘a reciprocal
recognition which is absolute
spirit’ (Phän 3:493/408). Here I would follow Pinkard: the idea is that
historically developing self-conscious beings will inevitably come to face
the problem of ‘groundlessness’ and to embrace the project of
‘self-grounding’ (1994: 269).
And third, these claims about our historical
development are supposed to be independent of our biological nature. They
would remain true if we were composed of different elements, for example.
Granted, Hegel’s spirit is not unconditioned in Kant’s sense. For the
existence of spirit depends on the existence of nature; we could not exist
without there being a nature in which we are embodied. Hegel’s claim,
however, is that whatever the natural conditions happen to be does not
decisively shape our historical development.
For example, even if thinking and self-conscious beings were made of
entirely different natural elements, they would still work their way into
conflicts concerning tradition and authority—just as we actually have.
Spirit, then, is conditioned, in the sense that its existence depends on the
existence of something else; but the nature of spirit is not determined by
anything outside itself.
I should note that I borrow heavily here from
non-metaphysical interpreters who stress Hegel’s claims about the free
self-determination of Geist.
But I am arguing that these claims are best understood as part of a
metaphysical theory. Granted, part of the point of Hegel’s account of spirit
is that what we are depends on how we develop over time, and that this
depends on our own thoughts and especially our thoughts about what we
ourselves are and should be.
But this is not a claim that is supposed to be limited to an account of how
we understand ourselves, or an account of our conceptual scheme, remaining
neutral about metaphysical questions. It is a metaphysical account of what
we ourselves really are, and how we relate and compare to everything else—it
is part of Hegel’s broader metaphysical account of the broader structure of
reality itself, or his larger account of natural kinds and levels of being.
This is all too brief, to be sure. But for my purposes
what is crucial is that Geist is
in some ways akin to a natural kind or
Gattung, and especially to a
biological species-kind; but also that
Geist is also distinguished from
such natural kinds by a kind of
free or independent development:
Geist is ‘free kind [Gattung]
coming into existence for itself’ (EL §222).
IV. Hegel Rejects Metaphysical Rationalism, Including Rationalist Monism
I now return to my central question: how do the
lower-levels of nature fit into the overall organization of all the levels
of being? More specifically, do they find a ground or reason in the
organization of the whole? That is to say, are the lower levels as they are
specifically because of the way they are to fit into the whole of reality?
That is the view that Hegel would have to hold if he were a rationalist
monist, holding that everything real must have a complete ground or reason,
ultimately provided by the whole. But does he hold it?
We are now in a position to see why this cannot be
Hegel’s view. The basic reason is this: we saw above that precisely what
distinguishes the lower level natural kinds is that they
lack any complete reason or
ground.
Still, there might seem to be room to propose the
following way of reading Hegel as a rationalist monist: Perhaps Hegel holds
that objects on the lower-levels of nature receive no complete ground or
reason at that level of nature;
but (so the story would run) insofar as all lower-level objects are merely
dependent, they must ultimately be dependent on some complete ground or
reason at a higher level of being.
One might think that this must be Hegel’s point. There
is something ‘distressing’ (Armstrong) or ‘strangely insubstantial’
(Chalmers) about the idea of things which are entirely dependent, without
any of them being independent enough for something else ultimately to depend
upon it. So we might well think that it would be too strange or distressing
to hold that lower-level physical reality is like that. How could Hegel
avoid this strange conclusion? Since he locates what is lacking—independent
substantiality—on the higher levels of being, he would have to do so by
concluding that the lower levels depend on the higher. For example, he might
hold that the whole network of lower-level kinds and laws is itself akin to
a biological organism. In an organism like a tiger, for example, there is
supposed to be an end intrinsic to the whole that explains why it has the
parts it does, and how those parts are related—why it has a heart, and
lungs, and why these parts are related as they are. Similarly, Hegel might
hold that the whole network of natural kinds and laws has an intrinsic end
that explains why there are distinct kinds, and why they are related as they
are. Or perhaps Hegel holds that the whole network of laws and kinds is
somehow akin instead to a thinking and self-conscious being, or to spirit.
In any case, it is crucial that such an account would require concluding
that lower-level natural kinds only
seem to lack a complete ground or reason in a self-determining totality.
What is really lacking would be the
conception of them as lacking anything independently substantial. The
truth would have to be that
lower-level natural objects have a hidden side, which reveals them to be
grounded in the manner of the parts of a whole that is more akin to a
self-determining biological whole, or even a spiritual whole.
But this is precisely what we do
not find in Hegel’s discussions
of the lower levels of nature. Instead of dispelling or filling the lack
substantiality at the lower levels of nature with an account of a hidden
dependence on higher-level substantiality, Hegel asserts that the lower
levels are nature really are strangely insubstantial. Consider again
‘Observing Reason.’ Here Hegel does not hold that there is something
inadequate or incomplete about the
conception or image of lower
level natural kinds as lacking a complete ground or reason. Rather, Hegel’s
point is that lower-level natural things are
themselves lacking insofar as
they really lack a complete
ground or reason. For example, looking back at a central passage from above:
an animal:
[M]aintains itself
for itself and detached from the
generality … What, however stands on a still lower level cannot itself any
longer distinguish itself from another, but in being contrasted with it gets
lost (Phän 3:190/149).
Lower-level natural objects lose
themselves, as it were, in chains of dependence on others; this is to say
that they do not find themselves
in any termination of those chains. If there is no termination, then there
is no termination in a larger whole, nor specifically a hidden higher-level
whole. Hegel’s point is that lower-level natural objects truly
differ from biological phenomena.
The point is precisely not that lower-level natural objects have a hidden
side that reveals them to parts of a whole that is biological or
similar to the biological. Hegel
is contrasting the real natures
of the inorganic and the organic. For example, after again underlining the
dependence of the inorganic, Hegel says that ‘in the organic being, on the
contrary, every deteminateness through which it is open to an other is
controlled by the organic, simply unity’ (Phän 3:196/154).
Hegel, then, cannot be a metaphysical rationalist of
any sort. For he holds that some things lack a complete ground or reason.
More specifically, there is no complete reason why any given lower-level
natural kind reacts with others as it does, nor any reason why there are
diverse lower-level natural kinds, nor any reason why these kinds are
arranged as they are in just this network of laws. Further, if Hegel is not
a metaphysical rationalist, then he cannot advocate rationalist monism in
particular. If some things lack an underlying ground or reason, then it
cannot be the case that there is any single ground of everything real—not in
the whole of all reality, nor anywhere else.
Similar considerations apply to Hegel’s general
contrast between nature and Geist.
Even the highest sort of natural kind, a biological species, fails to be a
self-determining totality. For its nature is shaped by and therefore
dependent on the external environment. And to say that it is dependent on
something external is to say that
there is no underlying ground or reason for why the species and the
environment are all arranged as they are. If there were such a ground of
these relationships in the whole of nature, then this would establish an
internal or intrinsic connection
between the different species and their environments. But to say, by
contrast, that a species is shaped by something merely
external is to say that it is in
a sense merely contingent: there is no underlying reason that determines or
necessitates the natures and
relations between the different species. Hegel says:
In nature, not only is the play of forms a
prey to boundless and unchecked contingency, but each separate entity is
without the concept of itself. The highest level to which nature attains is
life; but this, as only a natural mode of the idea, is at the mercy of the
unreason of externality … whereas in every expression of
Geist there is contained the
moment of free, universal self-relation. (PN §248An)
In contrasting nature and Geist,
Hegel is not saying that there is something limited or incomplete about the
image or
conception of nature in terms of
such contingency and external determination; he is saying that nature and
natural things themselves are limited or incomplete insofar as they
truly
are characterized by externality
and contingency in these senses.
Hegel sometimes makes this general point about the
limitations of nature itself by referring to a ‘powerlessness’ or ‘weakness’
or ‘impotence [Ohnmacht]
of nature.’ This is not to say that there is a weakness in our
conceiving nature in terms of
contingency and externality; rather, insofar as nature is
truly characterized by
contingency and externality, and lack of mediation by any complete
determining ground or reason, there is in this respect a kind of weakness in
nature itself:
In the sphere of
nature contingency and determination
from without has its right, and this contingency is at its greatest in the
realm of concrete individual forms, which however,
as products of nature, are
concrete only in an immediate manner … This
is the powerlessness of nature. (PN §250)
Alternatively, nature contains real contingency, in the
sense that it contains things that are not necessitated by any underlying
ground or reason. For example, take the lower-level natural kinds: no
underlying ground or reason necessitates the actual network of kinds; it is
merely contingent.
Of course, Hegel does
claim that reality as a whole has a structure or organization. Just not
in the sense that everything is as it is in virtue of its place within a
whole—not in the sense that the whole provides a complete reason or ground
for everything. Rather, reality is organized insofar as it has the structure
of a series of levels. And the levels differ precisely insofar as things on
different levels either have or lack
complete grounds or reasons to different degrees. Similarly, Hegel argues
that the whole of everything is similar to a biological organism in the
specific respect that both have a structure, or an organization. But the
whole of everything is not organized in the same sense that a living being
is supposed to be organized—not in the sense that any purpose or end
inherent in the whole explains why its parts are as they are. Rather, the
levels of being are distinct insofar as there are many phenomena that
differ from the biological in
this respect, including the lower-level natural kinds for which there is no
further explanation or reason in any larger whole or anywhere else.
In sum, Hegel advocates an ambitious metaphysics, an
account of the structure of reality; but it is a metaphysics that involves
the rejection of rationalist monism and all forms of metaphysical
rationalism.
V. Objections and Replies Concerning the Absolute and Nature’s
Dependence
One obvious objection to my interpretation above is the
following: Metaphysical interpretations tend to agree that Hegel’s
‘absolute’ is supposed to be the totality of everything real.
Further, the absolute cannot be something itself merely conditioned or
dependent, else it would not be absolute. Nor could the absolute have parts
that lack a sufficient ground or reason, else it would not be absolute. And
so it seems that Hegel must hold the metaphysical rationalist view that
everything real has a complete ground or reason: the absolute.
I would reply, however, that this objection itself
provides excellent reason to doubt that Hegel’s ‘absolute’ is supposed to
encompass everything. For we have seen that the lack of such complete
grounds or reasons is supposed to truly characterize the lower levels of
nature. So if the absolute cannot have parts that lack sufficient ground or
reason, then the lower levels of nature cannot be part of the absolute. On
my account, the concept of the absolute is the concept of something
self-determining. Insofar as the lower levels of nature do not satisfy this
concept, they are neither absolute nor part of the absolute. Insofar as
biological life only incompletely satisfies this concept, it is only an
approximation of the absolute. Insofar as the concept of independent
self-determination is satisfied completely only by
Geist or spirit, it follows that
the only thing truly absolute is spirit, or that ‘the absolute is
spirit—this is the supreme definition of the absolute’ (PG §384).
The same line of response can be expressed in terms of
Hegel’s relation to Spinoza. Spinoza defines substance as ‘that which is in
itself, and is conceived through itself’ (Ethics
1D3). Hegel argues that the whole of all reality cannot meet Spinoza’s
definition. For the whole of everything includes lower-level natural
phenomena lacking any complete ground or reason anywhere in the whole, so
that the whole of everything cannot, in this sense, be conceived entirely
through itself. But there is at least one sense in which
something meets Spinoza’s
definition: Geist or spirit does
so, at least in a sense. Granted, spirit is conditioned: it requires, for
its existence, that there is a nature within which it is embodied. Still,
spirit is supposed to be
self-determining in a manner that allows its development and the resulting
shapes of spirit to be ‘conceived through,’ or explained by appeal to,
spirit itself. So there is one sense in which
Geist or spirit is supposed to
meet Spinoza’s definition. Spirit—not the whole of everything—is the only
thing that, in this sense, ‘is in itself, and is conceived through itself.’
I would argue that this is what Hegel has in mind, in the famous lines from
the ‘Preface’ to the Phenomenology:
‘That the true is actual only as system, or that substance
is essentially subject, is
expressed in the representation of the absolute as spirit’ (Phän 3:28/14).
But in my view the most worrying objection is the
following: On my account, Hegel holds that lower-level natural objects do
not depend on anything at the higher levels—not on anything biological nor
on spirit. But there are certainly passages in which Hegel
seems to claim that the phenomena
of nature are grounded in an inner side that is itself spiritual or akin to
some kind of self-consciousness. A striking example, from ‘Force and the
Understanding’ in the Phenomenology,
concerns explanation of nature:
The understanding’s ‘explanation’ is
primarily only the description of what self-consciousness is … The reason
that ‘explaining’ affords so much self-satisfaction is just because in it
consciousness is, so to speak, communing directly with itself (Phän
3:133-4/101).
If explaining nature requires describing self-consciousness, then this
certainly seems to suggest that nature really depends on self-consciousness
or spirit.
Is nature supposed to depend on spirit in some sense?
Any good Hegelian would of course like to answer both ‘yes’ and ‘no.’ I too
would like to give both answers. But I think it crucial to explain
philosophically how the answer can be both yes and no—or how a single,
coherent and philosophical view could combine those answers. Again, at the
end of the day, we need something more to say than just that Hegel’s view is
dialectical, for that would leave us still in need of an explanation of this
terminology and how it pulls off the trick.
I have already argued that, insofar as the question
about nature depending on spirit is a metaphysical question, the answer is
‘no’: lower-level natural kinds and laws do not really depend on spirit or
any higher level phenomena; there is no further explanation of why such
kinds are as they are, not even an explanation appealing to spirit. But this
leaves room for Hegel to answer that nature does depend upon spirit in a
sense that is compatible because it is epistemological and not metaphysical.
I do not mean by this that the knowability of nature depends on spirit.
Rather, the intelligibility of nature—that natural phenomena can be
comprehended and explained at all—depends on their place within a whole that
includes spirit.
To see the point, consider Kant’s account of the
faculty of reason. Say we know about something conditioned, X. We are
supposed to take an interest in explaining X, specifically by seeking its
underlying conditions. We might then discover its underlying condition, Y,
where this too is something merely conditioned. Now our interest in
explanation cannot simply be satisfied by this discovery. Otherwise we would
have already been satisfied to begin with. For knowledge of Y is precisely
like our prior knowledge of X in the respect that originally left us wanting
an explanation: Y is again something merely conditioned. So our interest in
explanation must be an interest in something more than just uncovering
underlying conditions. On Kant’s account, it is an interest in following the
series of conditions to completion,
establishing knowledge of something
unconditioned. As noted above, Kant rules out the possibility of
knowledge of anything unconditioned. But Kant nonetheless argues that we can
and must continue to seek to uncover underlying conditions. I take the point
to be that we can at least in this way make progress in explaining things:
insofar as we can follow a series of underlying conditions, we are at least
heading in the direction of the ultimate goal—even if we cannot reach the
goal. Although Kant’s view here is complex, he certainly does argue that the
faculty of reason provides the goals guiding our natural scientific inquiry,
and that we can only approach these goals ‘asymptotically, as it were, i.e.,
merely by approximation, without ever reaching them’ (A663/B691).
Now compare Hegel’s accounts of the lower levels of
nature. Imagine that we ask why some acid neutralizes some base. Here we can
discover that the observed substance is an instance of the natural kind
acid, and we can discover the law
requiring an acid to neutralize a base. But there is an excellent reason to
worry that this cannot amount to an
explanation. After all, we have only said that this stuff neutralizes
that stuff because the nature of this stuff is to neutralize that stuff. On
the face of it, the explanatory question still stands unanswered insofar as
we have nothing more to say about why
acids neutralize bases. And yet we can go no farther with such phenomena: on
Hegel’s account, there is no further ground or reason to be discovered on
this level for why there are different natural kinds, and why they are
linked as they are by laws. So there is a threat that there is no
explanation to be had on this level, or the lower levels of nature. Of
course, today the physical sciences can proceed farther here, uncovering the
underlying chemical structure. But our progress just brings out how dire the
worry is: Our drive for further knowledge is testament to the point that
just ceasing with a system of natural laws and kinds does not itself satisfy
our interest in explanation. And yet we ourselves
cannot ever reach results that
are different in the specific respect that leaves our interest in
explanation unsatisfied—that is the point I borrowed from contemporary
accounts above—so long as we must stop somewhere with a system of supposedly
basic natural laws and kinds.
I have argued elsewhere (2004) that this basic worry
about explanation drives Hegel’s progress in his account of the lowest level
of nature, mechanism. Imagine as a thought experiment the possibility that
everything is explicable in
lowest-level mechanistic terms and that is all. Hegel argues that there
would then be no substance to the notion of explanation itself—the notion of
‘explanation’, Hegel says, would be a merely ‘empty word’ (WL 6:413/713-4).
So insofar as we take anything to be intelligible or explicable at all,
there must be more to reality than just mechanism.
What difference will it make if Hegel is correct that
there exists more than just the lower-levels of nature—that there also
exists spirit, and that spirit is independently self-determining in the
sense discussed above? I have said that this changes nothing in Hegel’s
metaphysics of nature: nature is not spirit, and does not really depend on
spirit or anything spiritual or in any sense quasi-spiritual. So what can
any of this change about nature and its explanation? The answer is that we
can understand nature differently when we view it in context of the whole
hierarchy of levels, including spirit. In that context, we can understand
the whole network of lower-level natural kinds as related, if only
distantly, to the kind of self-determining totality actually found in the
case of spirit. For example, in learning the basic natural kind of
something, and the laws connecting that kind to others, we locate things
within a broader whole system of laws and kinds. As I have emphasized, this
system is ‘not yet’ the sort of ‘totality of self-determination’ that might
completely satisfy our interest in explanation (WL 6:434/731-2). But the
whole network of laws and kinds is at least a distant echo of that kind of
self-determining system. And so there is a sense in which we can at least
make progress when seeking to explain lower-level natural phenomena: in
discovering natural kinds and laws we can explain insofar as we can begin to
travel in the direction that would completely satisfy our interest in
explanation, if we could go further. Note the differences as compared to
Kant’s account of our progress in the explanation of nature: First, what
prevents us from going further is not, as with Kant, an epistemic
limitation—it is rather a limitation of this level itself: on this lower
level there is nowhere further to go. Second, on Hegel’s account our goal is
not knowledge of something completely unconditioned; it is knowledge of
something that independently determines its own nature (even if it may be
conditioned in the sense of depending on other things for its existence).
One way that Hegel expresses this view of nature is by
means of his term ‘the idea.’ ‘The idea’ refers to whole systems for which
understanding the whole—or ‘the concept’ [Begriff]
of the whole—provides an explanation of how the whole relates to the
concrete or objective parts in a manner that is self-determining. ‘The idea’
is, Hegel says, ‘the absolute unity
of concept and objectivity’ (EL §213). The biological level provides the
first realization of what Hegel calls ‘the idea’: ‘the idea is firstly life’
(WL 6:468/760). But the only complete realization of the idea is spirit:
again, biological life, ‘as only a natural mode of the idea, is at the mercy
of the unreason of externality … whereas in every expression of
Geist there is contained the
moment of free, universal self-relation (PN §248An). We can find only very
distant echoes of ‘the idea’ in even the lowest-level of nature. In Hegel’s
terms, nature is ‘the idea in the
form of otherness’—nature is different or other than the idea, it is
‘external in relation to this idea’ (PN §247). But we can explain nature
insofar as what we find there is at least related, if only distantly, to
‘the idea.’
The basic epistemological point, then, is this: Imagine
that there were only lower-level natural kinds—that they exhaust nature and
everything. Under those conditions, there would be no sense in which we
could make progress in seeking to explain nature. But this is not all that
there is, and there is a sense in which we can make such progress. Insofar
as we identify natural kinds and governing laws, we take a step toward
uncovering the sort of self-determining kind. The idea of such a
self-determining kind is not just
something we imagine that has nothing to do with reality; nor is it an idea
of something of which we could never have knowledge. Rather, Hegel argues
that the real world does satisfy just this idea:
Geist is real and is such a
self-determining kind, and we can find more and less distant approximations
of such self-determination elsewhere throughout nature. This is the sense in
which explaining nature means finding traces of ourselves within it. And
that is why Hegel says that the reason ‘‘explaining’ affords so much
self-satisfaction is just because in it consciousness is, so to speak,
communing directly with itself’ (PhG 3:133-4/101).
VI. Conclusion
Of course, there can be no question of giving here a
comprehensive explanation or decisive defense of an interpretation of all
the major points of Hegel’s entire theoretical philosophy. What I have
argued is that careful attention to what Hegel says about the lower levels
of nature, especially in ‘Observing Reason’ from the
Phenomenology, opens the
possibility of a surprising approach to Hegel’s broader theoretical
philosophy—an approach that is surprising in that it can actually
incorporate the strongest points from both sides in recent debates about
Hegel and metaphysics.
On the one hand, non-metaphysical interpreters are
correct to claim that Hegel rejects as dogmatic a form of metaphysics of
central concern to Kant: Hegel entirely rejects metaphysical rationalism,
including monist forms of metaphysical rationalism. Hegel is not out to
revive Spinoza, at least not in the sense of seeking to revive a monist form
of metaphysical rationalism. Hegel holds that there is no single ground of
all reality—not even in the whole of everything.
On the other hand, none of this requires us to hold
that Hegel’s project is non-metaphysical. We can still recognize that Hegel
claims to discern the structure or organization of reality itself. We can
even recognize that Hegel provides a metaphysical account of a highest or
most fundamental being: not in the sense that there is one ground on which
all reality depends, or in which all reality finds a reason or a ground; but
there is something, on Hegel’s account, that is highest in being completely
self-determining—namely, spirit. And, on Hegel’s account, all other levels
of being are more and less distant approximations of this complete
self-determination.
And then on yet another hand—hopefully one may appeal
to three hands in an interpretation of Hegel—even given all this ambitious
metaphysics, we can return and say that non-metaphysical interpreters are
correct in another respect: Hegel does hold that nature depends on spirit in
an epistemological and not a metaphysical sense. But the point here is not
that the knowability of nature depends on spirit. Rather, the
intelligibility of nature depends on the reality of self-determining spirit.
In sum, neither side in recent debates need get the
short end of the stick, or the short end of the
Aufhebung, as it were. There is
an approach to Hegel’s theoretical philosophy according to which the
strongest interpretive points on both sides can be preserved, and need not
be cancelled.
James Kreines
Department of Philosophy
Claremont McKenna
College
850 Columbia Avenue
Claremont, CA 91711
jkreines@cmc.edu
Primary Texts / Abbreviations
A/B: Kant, Immanuel (1998), Critique of Pure Reason. P. Guyer and A. Wood
trs., Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. Aside from references to the Critique of Pure Reason.
Ak: All other references to Kant’s writings are given by volume and page
number of the Akademie edition of Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften (Berlin: de
Gruyter, 1902-).
EL: Hegel, G.W.F (1991), Encyclopaedia Logic. T.F Geraets, H.S Harris, and
W.A Suchting trs., Hackett Publishing Co. Indiana. Encyclopedia cited by §
number, with ‘An’ indicating Anmerkung and ‘Zu’ indicating the Zusatz. All
other references to Hegel’s writings are given by volume and page number of
Hegel, G.W.F (1970-1), Werke in zwanzig Bände. E. Moldernhauer und K. Michel
eds., Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Ethics: Spinoza, B. (1994), A Spinoza Reader. E. Curley ed., and tr.,
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Phän: Hegel, G.W.F (1977), Phenomenology of Spirit A..V. Miller tr.,
Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
PG: Hegel, G.W.F (1971), Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind. W. Wallace and A. V.
Miller trs., New York:
Oxford University Press.
PN: Hegel, G.W.F (1970), Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature.W. Wallace and A. V.
Miller trs., New York:
Oxford University Press.
PP: Hegel, G.W.F (1986), The Philosophical Propaedeutic. M. George & A.
Vincent, eds., A. V. Miller, tr.
Oxford, Blackwell.
VGP: Hegel, G.W.F (1995), Lectures on the History of Philosophy. 3 vols. E.
S. Haldane and F. H. Simson trs., Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
VPA: Hegel, G.W.F (1975), Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. 3 vols. T.M.Knox
tr., Oxford: Clarendon Press.
WL: Hegel, G.W.F (1969), Hegel’s
Science of Logic.
A.V. Miller tr., London: George Allen & Unwin.
Other Works Cited
Armstrong, D. M. (1993),
A Materialist Theory of the Mind.
Routledge, London.
Beiser, F.C. (1993), ‘Introduction: Hegel
and the Problem of Metaphysics’, in
The Cambridge Companion to Hegel. Beiser, F. C. ed. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Beiser, F.C. (2005), Hegel.
London: Routledge.
Blackburn, S. (1990), ‘Filling in Space’,
Analysis 50, 62-5.
Brandom, R. (1999), ‘Some Pragmatist
Themes in Hegel's Idealism’, European
Journal of Philosophy,
7,164-189.
Chalmers, D. (1996) The Conscious Mind.
New York: Oxford UP.
Hartmann, K. (1972), ‘Hegel: a
Non-metaphysical View’, in A. MacIntyre ed.,
Hegel: A Collection Of Critical
Essays. Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press.
Hegel, G.W.F (1995), Lectures on the History of Philosophy. 3 vols.
E. S. Haldane and F. H. Simson trs., Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Hegel, G.W.F (1969), Hegel’s Science
of Logic. A.V. Miller tr., London: George Allen & Unwin.
Hegel, G.W.F (1970), Hegel’s
Philosophy of Nature.W. Wallace and A. V. Miller trs., New York: Oxford
University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F
(1970-1), Werke in zwanzig Bände.
E.
Moldernhauer und K. Michel eds., Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Hegel, G.W.F (1971), Hegel’s
Philosophy of Mind. W. Wallace and A. V. Miller trs., New York: Oxford
University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F (1975), Aesthetics:
Lectures on Fine Art. T.M.Knox tr., 3 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hegel, G.W.F (1977), Phenomenology of
Spirit A..V. Miller tr., Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F (1986), The Philosophical Propaedeutic. M. George & A. Vincent,
eds., A. V. Miller, tr. Oxford, Blackwell.
Hegel, G.W.F (1991),
Encyclopaedia Logic. T.F Geraets,
H.S Harris, and W.A Suchting trs., Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.
Horstmann, R. P. (1991), Die Grenzen der
Vernunft. Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen und Motiven des Deutschen Idealismus.
Frankfurt am Main: Anton Hain.
Horstmann, R. P. (1998/2004), ‘Hegel,
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich’, in E. Craig ed.,
Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. London: Routledge. <http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/DC036>
Kant, Immanuel (1998),
Critique of Pure Reason. P. Guyer
and A. Wood trs., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kreines, J. (2004), ‘Hegel’s Critique of
Pure Mechanism’, European Journal of
Philosophy. 12:1, 38-74.
Kreines, J. (2007), ‘Between The Bounds
of Experience and Divine Intuition: Kant’s Epistemic Limits and Hegel’s
Ambitions’, Inquiry 50:3, 306 -
334.
Kreines, J. (2008), ‘The Logic of Life:
Hegel’s Philosophical Defense of Teleological Explanation in Biology’ in F.
Beiser, ed., The Cambridge Companion
to Hegel and Nineteenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lin, M. 2007. ‘Spinoza's Arguments for
the Existence of God’, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research. 75: 2. 269-297.
Pinkard, T. (1994),
Hegel's Phenomenology. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Pippin, R. (1989),
Hegel’s Idealism. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Pippin, R. (1991),
Modernism as a Philosophical Problem:
On the Dissatisfactions of European High Culture. Oxford: Blackwell.
Redding, P. (1996),
Hegel's Hermeneutics. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
Russell, B. (1954),
The Analysis of Matter. 2nd
ed. Dover, New York: Allen & Unwin.
Spinoza, B. (1994),
A Spinoza Reader. E. Curley ed.,
and tr., Princetone: Princeton University Press.
Stern, R. (1990), Hegel, Kant and the
Structure of the Object. London: Routledge.
Taylor, C. (1975),
Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Westphal, K. R. (1989),
Hegel's Epistemological Realism.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Some hold that Hegel
sees this ground of everything as a mind or spirit [‘Geist’]
or ‘subject’ which is somehow freely self-creating (e.g. Taylor
1975: 87ff.). Others understand Hegel’s modification of Spinoza in
this way: everything real is determined by a fundamental organizing
principle of the whole, which interpreters often call a basic
‘structure.’ This is supposed to be what Hegel himself refers to as
‘the idea.’ It is not
itself a mind; it is an organizing principle which governs both
natural and mental phenomena, although it is more completely
realized in the latter. See Horstmann on ‘primary structure’ (1991:
177-82) and the similar formulation at (1998/2004: Part 4). And see
Beiser on Hegel’s modification of Spinoza’s monism (1993 and 2005).
Hartmann: ‘Hegel
advocates a ‘modest … hermeneutic of categories,’ or ‘a
non-metaphysical philosophy devoid of existence claims and innocent
of a reductionism opting for certain existences to the determinant
of others’ (1972: 124 and 110). Later non-metaphysical interpreters
differ in many respects but also read Hegel’s project as focused not
on metaphysical issues but on our concepts and their legitimacy. For
example, Pippin: ‘Most of
Hegel's significant revisions of Kant involve his
transformation of Kant's theory of
concepts, his
reinterpretation of Kant's account of the
objectivity of concepts,
and his different treatment of the notion of
subjectivity relevant to
an idealist version of such issues.’ (1989: 7). Hegel follows what
Brandom describes as a Kantian ‘shift in attention from ontological
questions … to deontological ones’ (1999: 165).
See Lin on
‘metaphysical rationalism’ and Spinoza (2007).
In short, our merely
‘discursive’ understanding is dependent for all intuition on the
faculty of sensibility and the
a priori forms of
sensibility, space and time (e.g. B135; Prolegomena
Ak 4:288); and the forms of space and time prevent
theoretical having knowledge of anything unconditioned. E.g. ‘In
sensibility, i.e. in space and time, every condition to which we can
attain in the exposition of given appearances is in turn
conditioned’ (A508/B536).
We are subject to ‘a
natural and unavoidable illusion which itself rests on
subjective principles and passes them off as objective’ (A298/B354).
‘If something, no
matter what, exists, then it must also be conceded that something
exists
necessarily. For the contingent exists only under the
condition of something else as its cause, and from this the same
inference holds further all the way to a cause not existing
contingently and therefore necessarily without condition. That is
the argument on which reason grounds its progress to the original
being’ [Urwesen].
Although this argument must be rejected, it is also ‘the natural
course taken by every human reason’ (A584-5/B612-3).
Although I agree with
much else in Beiser’s metaphysical interpretation, on this
particular point I disagree (see 2005: 55).
On the principle of
sufficient reason in Spinoza’s argument for the existence of God,
see Lin 2007.
So I agree with
non-metaphysical readers when they make this point specifically. For
example, Pippin: Hegel ‘enthusiastically agreed with Kant that the
metaphysics of the ‘beyond,’ of substance, and of traditional views
of God and infinity were forever discredited’ (1989: 7). Redding: Hegel’s view is ‘at variance with the
Spinozistic form of holism on which Schelling had drawn’ (1996:
108–109).
On Hegel on the
mind-independence of such natural kinds see also Westphal (1989: Ch.
10) and Stern (1990).
The ‘Mechanism’
section in the Logic
concludes specifically with discussion of the law of gravity
governing the rotation of matter (EL §198; WL 6:423ff/721ff).
I generally translate
Hegel’s Gattung, used in
biological contexts, as ‘species’ or ‘kind’ rather than ‘genus’. One
case in which this is clearly the best translation is this: a living
individual ‘reproduces itself as another individual of the
same species or kind [Gattung]’
(PP 4:32/142).
And ‘species’ is the best translation where Hegel refers to the
propagation of the ‘species’ or ‘die
Fortpflanzung der Gattung’ (PN §365Zu p. 404/492).
The end is
preservation of the individual and of the species: ‘the end
of the animal in itself as an individual is its own
self-preservation; but its true end in itself is the species’ (VGP
20:87/3:185). See also EL §221 and WL 6:484/773-4.
See Hegel’s
connection between the concrete universal and Kant’s analysis of
inner purposiveness (WL 6:443/739). On this issue and the connection
to issues concerning logic, see especially Thompson (1995).
An addition to the
Philosophy of Geist
considers an example: ‘Geist,
as embodied, is indeed in a definite place and in a definite time …
the life of man is conditioned … he could not live at either a
greater or a lesser distance from the sun; but the influence of the
position of the Earth on mankind does not go beyond that’ (PG
§392Zu/p. 38).
See for example the
reference to Pinkard above and the reference to Pippin immediately
below.
I follow Pippin on this point: spirit is ‘self-forming
in time’ in the sense that our ‘criteria and values are the way they
are because of the determinate insufficiencies of prior attempts at
self-understanding and self-legitimation’ (1991: 68-9).
See also PN §250; PN §368Zu 9:510; PN §314Zu.
Beiser thinks that
the point raises a problem concerning Hegel’s account of
contingency. He provides an extremely compelling account of the
problem itself, and I agree—although I think that this is not a
problem for Hegel but rather a problem for the interpretation of
Hegel as a metaphysical rationalist. In any case, Beiser sees this
basic point—although it raises a problem—as ‘indisputable’:
‘the absolute is
all reality, having
nothing outside itself to limit it’ or ‘make it finite’ (2005: 76).
I would answer that Hegel’s absolute is supposed to be infinite in
the sense of infinitely self-determining or free. And only
Geist is infinite in this
sense. In Hegel’s terms: ‘The infinite is, and more intensely so
than the first immediate being … in the infinite the spirit is not
merely abstractly present to itself, but rises to its own self, to
the light of its thinking, of its universality, of its freedom’ (WL
5:150/137-8). Again, what is absolute or infinite is specifically
Geist. And so Hegel
refers to ‘that universal which as truly absolute concept is to be
grasped as the idea of infinite spirit’ (WL
6:494/780).
This paper has
benefited greatly from presentation and discussion with participants
at the 2007 conference of the Hegel Society of Great Brittan, and
from questions from, discussion with and comments by Fred Beiser,
Troy Cross, Steve Davis, Michael Della
Rocca, Robert Guay,
Robert Pippin, Paul Redding, and Bob Stern.
|