Hegel’s Critique of Pure Mechanism and the Philosophical Appeal of the
Logic Project
James Kreines
European Journal of Philosophy 12:1 (2004): pp.
38-74.
Subscribers can click here for published version. Please cite the
published version. What follows is a final draft. I give a newer
treatment of this material in Chapter 1 of Reason in
the World.
Hegel criticizes mechanistic explanation in both versions of
his Science of
Logic,1
assigning it a subordinate or inferior status: teleology, he says, is ‘the
truth of mechanism’ (WL 6:437-8/735). As always with Hegel, the meaning
of this claim is not immediately and transparently clear. Does mechanism
somehow describe or classify the world in a false, misleading, or unhelpful
way? Are mechanistic accounts supposed to be incomplete in some way which
prevents them from being truly explanatory? Or is Hegel’s complaint to be
understood in some other terms? And, whatever the claim, how could it possibly
be supported by any sort of a priori philosophical considerations, as
opposed to empirical consideration of how the world actually is?
What is clear is that Hegel connects his mechanism
argument directly to the conclusions of the Logic as a whole. In
particular, Hegel complains that conceiving objects in mechanistic terms
leaves ‘the notion’ merely ‘subjective’ or ‘outside’ of them (§195). Hegel
aims to defend, by contrast, ‘the absolute unity of notion and
objectivity,’ which he calls simply ‘the idea’ (§213). Needless to say,
this desired conclusion too stands in need of interpretation; it raises the
largest, most important and difficult interpretive questions concerning Hegel.
I undertake here the challenges of clarifying and defending
Hegel’s mechanism argument, and showing how it throws some much-needed light
on the nature and philosophical appeal of the Logic project. I will
argue that the key to all this is Hegel’s focus on a philosophical problem
concerning explanation itself. Unfortunately, this problem can easily
be obscured from us by contemporary tastes and assumptions. In particular,
where Hegel discusses mechanism and teleology, we must not read him as if he
meant to distinguish and examine something like two distinct but compatible
ways of describing or classifying the world so as to address our different
pragmatic or subjective interests. This reading would seriously constrain our
understanding of Hegel’s complaint about mechanism: the point would have to be
that mechanism inaccurately, incompletely, or unhelpfully describes the
world. Such a complaint would have to draw upon premises about the actual
world and its contents, and it is hard to see how these could be compelling
except as empirical claims.
But this approach gets off on the wrong foot. There may or may
not be philosophical benefits to the idea that different forms of explanation
are akin to compatible but distinct ways of describing or classifying the
world. But to attribute such a notion of explanation to Hegel is to
misunderstand his philosophy and its historical context. As is well-known,
Hegel draws his basic terminology for formulating the contrast between
mechanism and teleology from Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment
(KU). What is less well-recognized is that Kant’s contrast brings with it an
objective notion of explanation. Explaining, in the sense that
interests Kant and Hegel, involves more than just describing or classifying
objects or events in a manner which addresses whatever subjective interests we
might have; explaining requires identifying those factors which objectively
determine why events occur as they do, specifically in the manner that is
objectively most relevant to this determination of the course of events
(section 1 below).
This objective notion of explanation raises a series of
philosophical difficulties, beginning with the problem of accounting for the
distinction between the explanatory and the non-explanatory. In particular,
what makes something the most relevant way of accounting for an
explanandum, in contrast to the innumerably many ways of describing it which,
though perfectly true, do not explain it? For example, one might propose that
explanations are distinguished in virtue of describing explananda in terms
which subsume them under general laws. Or one might propose that they are
distinguished in virtue of identifying the underlying forces at work behind
the phenomena to be explained. Hegel’s mechanism argument itself does not
propose a solution of this sort. It rather exploits the problem in support of
a conclusion concerning mechanistic explanation in particular. The target of
Hegel’s attack is the idea that everything which can be explained at all can
ultimately be explained in mechanistic terms. Hegel argues that assuming
mechanism is ‘absolute’ in this sense would make the general problem
concerning explanation in principle irresolvable. That is, under the
conditions imposed by the assumption, there can be no way of accounting for
the distinction between explanation and description (section 2). Appeal to the
notion of causal or natural laws does not help, but rather brings out general
reasons to doubt that we can distinguish explanation in terms of any sort of
requirement on the form of individual explanations (section 3). Nor can
it help to expand our ontology to include a ‘real ground’—such as the force of
gravity—which is supposed to be distinct from or independent of the natural
phenomena to be explained (section 4).
The result, Hegel argues, is that the notion of explanation
itself is collapsed, or reduced to ‘only an empty word’ (WL
6:413/713-4). And that means we cannot after all coherently entertain the idea
that only mechanism might be explanatory; to try is to undercut the notion of
explanation needed to formulate that very proposal. So Hegel’s mechanism
complaint is neither that mechanism incompletely describes the world, nor that
mechanism cannot completely account for natural phenomena, such as the
rotation of matter around a center of gravity. His complaint is that making
mechanism ‘absolute’ would undermine any possible account of explanation
itself. And that means that mechanistic accounts will have to depend, for
whatever explanatory legitimacy they do have, on the legitimacy of some form
of teleology (section 5).
Investigating the premises of this argument leads, first of
all, to the central commitment of Hegel’s theoretical philosophy: to avoid any
foundational appeal to a supposed form of immediate self-justifying knowledge
(section 6). We can understand in these terms why Hegel’s mechanism argument
does not appeal to a proposed form of immediate knowledge of ourselves as
spontaneous, free, or otherwise non-mechanistic beings. And we can understand
why Hegel’s mechanism complaint is not and cannot be—contra a great many
interpretations—that mechanism fails because it cannot account for the
totality of everything there is in a perfectly complete manner. For Hegel does
not and cannot begin by appealing to any special immediate insight into the
supposed seamless unity and intelligibility of reality as a whole. In fact,
Hegel’s real argument is nearly the reverse: to suppose that mechanism alone
is explanatory (Hegel argues) would be to dissolve everything into one single
undifferentiated whole, leaving no way to grasp what it would be to explain
anything in particular.
Finally, these results show that we can and must move beyond
traditional approaches, both metaphysical and non-metaphysical, to Hegel’s
overall argument strategy. Hegel’s arguments are grounded in a genuinely
internal criticism of Kant, not in mere assumptions drawn from pre-Kantian
metaphysics. And yet to make good on this internal criticism would require
Hegel to go significantly beyond a non-metaphysical inquiry; he must attempt
to justify an account of ‘the absolute,’ or that which most fundamentally
exists—specifically in the sense of that in virtue of which true explanations
truly explain (section 7). I will conclude by posing some questions which can
narrow the interpretive options concerning the Logic’s conclusions
about the absolute, and concerning the nature of Hegel’s robust but unusual
idealism (section 8). In sum, careful consideration of Hegel’s focus on
problems concerning explanation will allow us to see how the Logic
itself might really be what Hegel means it to be: an extended philosophical
argument from non-question-begging premises to far-reaching and
controversial conclusions.
1. Problems Raised by the Objective Notion of Explanation in Kant and Hegel
I have outlined a complaint about mechanism based on a problem
concerning explanation; but why think that Hegel is really so concerned
about this problem? The answer begins with Kant’s KU discussion of the
contrast between teleology and mechanism, and Hegel’s response in the
‘Teleology’ section of the Logic—where Hegel praises Kant’s notion of
‘internal purposiveness’ (innere Zweckmäßigkeit)
as one of the most important ideas in Kant, and perhaps in all of
philosophy (WL 6:440-1/737; §204).
In the KU discussion which so influences Hegel, Kant uses the
term ‘mechanism’ to single out accounts which explain without reference to any
special organization, structure, or arrangement of whole systems. In other
words, mechanism explains the structure and behavior of the whole in terms of
the independent changes of the parts, and ultimately in terms of matter and
the natural laws governing it. For example: ‘if we consider a material whole,
as far as its form is concerned, as a product of the parts and of their forces
and their capacity to combine by themselves ... we represent a mechanical kind
of generation’ (KU
5:408).2
The results of such ‘mechanical kind of generation’ are
supposed to contrast with truly organized systems, or
Zwecke (‘purposes’ or ‘ends’). To be
organized in this sense, it is not enough merely to be truly describable
in teleological terms. To borrow Kant’s example, we might truly describe a
sea as depositing the sandy soil which benefits a forest of spruce trees (KU
5:367). But that is no reason to think that the sea deposits the soil in order
to benefit the trees—on account of that end or purpose. Such benefit gives us
no reason to doubt that the movements of sea and soil and their arrangement
relative to the spruce trees can all be explained perfectly well according to
a ‘mechanical kind of generation,’ without reference to benefit, purpose,
function,
etc.3
Matters would be different with respect to a system whose origin could not be
explained in terms of the independent changes of its parts, specifically
because its parts are present at all only on account of some role they play
within the whole. Thus we might explain in teleological terms—more
specifically by attributing functions or purposes to the parts of a
system—only where the ‘parts (as far as their existence and their form are
concerned) are possible only through their relation to the whole’ (KU 5:373).
And this organization requirement is Kant’s first step away from the merely
‘external purposiveness’ (äußere Zweckmäßigkeit) (KU 5:368) of sand and
sea-type cases, and toward the genuine ‘internal purposiveness’ which so
interests Hegel.
It is crucial that this specific contrast does not treat
teleology and mechanism as two different forms of description or
classification, but as two different forms of explanation: to apply either is
to purport to account, in the most relevant manner, for why a system is
as it is. And this generates a problem concerning their compatibility which is
of central concern to Kant. With respect to the origin of one single system,
its parts either are present on account of their roles within the whole, or
they are not and can be explained without any such reference. Concerning this
specific question there cannot be compatible but different perspectives or
points of view. As Kant says, ‘one kind of explanation excludes the other’ (KU
5:412).4
This is an incomplete look at Kant’s notion of internal
purposiveness, and I have ignored Kant’s own attempt to resolve the
philosophical problems by limiting teleological judgment of nature to a merely
subjective validity—to ‘reflective’ judgment serving a ‘regulative’ function
but unsuitable for explanation in the objective sense
(Erklärung).5
Discussions of Hegel’s response often begin with Hegel’s rejection of that
conclusion, especially as this rejection is expressed in Hegel’s early
Glauben und Wissen
(1802).6
But the right way to understand Hegel’s response to Kant, at least in the
Logic, is to begin with a continuity: Hegel’s arguments may aim at very
different conclusions, but they are driven everywhere by an appropriation of
Kant’s basic contrast and the objective notion of explanation carried with it.
Thus Hegel too treats mechanism and teleology as forms of explanation in the
objective sense: both purport to get at the why or the because of things.
Hegel does not treat them as ways of describing or classifying things which
would be mutually ‘indifferent,’ in that one and the same object could be
truly described in many different ways, legitimately classified using
different conceptual schemes, etc. More specifically, Hegel says that
mechanism and teleology cannot
be taken as indifferent concepts,
each of which is for itself a correct notion, in possession of as much
validity as the other, the only question being where one or the other can be
applied. This equal validity of both is grounded merely because they
are, that is to say, because we have them both. (WL 6:437/735)
So Hegel too sees the contrast, built
on an objective notion of explanation, as a source of philosophical problems.
It means that teleology and mechanism are not merely distinct and
‘indifferent’ ways of conceptualizing the world; they threaten to conflict.
And it means that questions about their justification or legitimacy
specifically as forms of explanation cannot be addressed just by reflecting on
the forms of description or classification which we ‘have’ or tend to prefer
and find of interest in different cases.
How will Hegel approach these philosophical problems? He is
clear, at least, what he will not do. For he criticizes the approach of
‘earlier metaphysics’: ‘it has for one thing presupposed a certain
representation of the world (Weltvorstellung) and labored to show that
one or the other concept fitted it, while the opposite one was defective’ (WL
6:437/734). But one assumption is only as good as another, and merely
presupposing a basic picture of the nature of reality cannot possibly resolve
philosophical questions concerning mechanism and teleology. So it is a mistake
to see Hegel as interested in examining the compatibility of mechanism or
teleology with one or another
Weltvorstellung. For example, Hegel will not
evaluate mechanism in terms of its compatibility with a common-sense picture
of the world, which might suggest difficulties when it comes specifically to
living beings, our own actions, etc. Nor will he evaluate mechanism in terms
of its incompatibility with a picture of reality as a completely intelligible
whole, a single unified mind, or single developmental mental process, etc.
Instead, Hegel promises to approach directly what he calls ‘the notion
(Begriff) of mechanical cause and of end’ with an eye to determining
‘which possesses truth in and for itself’ (WL 6:437/734). Of course, we
have seen enough to know that the point is not to ask the degree to which
mechanism and/or teleology are true descriptions of the world; the
point is to evaluate the truth of their claims to explain, to get at
the why or because of things.
We are interested specifically in the first step of this
extended inquiry, namely, in Hegel’s investigation of the claim of mechanism
in particular to explain. How can Hegel approach this topic directly, without
bringing to bear either empirical data or mere assumptions about the world? He
does so by means of a thought experiment. The hypothesis to be tested is that
everything explainable can be explained in mechanistic terms. I’ll call this
the ‘total mechanism’ hypothesis. Is it possible, Hegel asks, to make sense of
mechanism’s claim to explain, as opposed to merely describe, while staying
within the bounds of that thought experiment? Hegel argues that we can answer
‘no’ on philosophical grounds. For the total mechanism hypothesis will render
the general problem of explanation in principle irresolvable. That is, within
these bounds there can be no way to successfully account for the distinction
between explanation and description, and so there can be no genuine notion of
explanation at all. In Hegel’s terms, the Logic tests whether different
‘logical determinations’ might succeed as ‘definitions of the absolute’
(§85).7
He will argue that ‘the mechanical point of view must be rejected quite
decisively when it pretends to take the place of comprehensive cognition
generally, and to establish mechanism as absolute category
(als absolute Kategorie)’ (§195Z).
Or so Hegel will argue. But how? After all, accounting for
explanation itself presents a perfectly general philosophical problem; why
should it have any special significance concerning mechanistic explanation in
particular? As we will see, the answer turns on the implications total
mechanism would have concerning concepts which discriminate
individuals.
2. The General Case: Mechanism and the Problem of Merely External Notions
Hegel begins with Kant’s definition, according to which
mechanism is explanation of wholes as the ‘product of the parts and of their
forces and their capacity to combine by themselves’ (KU 5:408). To imagine
such explanation alone is legitimate, and legitimate everywhere, is to imagine
that everything explainable is a composite of independent, non-coordinated
parts. So even if the relationship between parts suggests ‘a semblance of
unity,’ Hegel says, ‘it remains nothing more than composition, mixture,
aggregation and the like’ (WL 6:410/711; also §195). Furthermore, for any two
or more objects, we can think of the larger whole system they constitute
together, and this too will have to be merely an aggregate of independent
parts. Thus the original objects must be operating independently of one
another. In Hegel’s terms, ‘whatever relation obtains between the things
combined, this relation is one foreign to them that does not concern their
nature’ (WL
6:409/711).8
Now consider the implications of this point concerning concepts
which discriminate individuals. We might approach Hegel’s claim via an
example. It is not an arbitrary matter whether I apply the concept black
or the concept pink to my cat, because she is black and not pink.
But should I consider her as a whole, in terms of the concept cat? If
the total-mechanism hypothesis is correct, then she is an aggregate of
independent non-coordinated parts. So I might just as well consider her as a
bunch of atoms. What’s more, the relations between those parts of my cat will
be no different than their relations with everything else, so I might as well
consider her instead as a tiny part of everything in this room, this
continent, solar system, galaxy, etc. Or even as a tiny part of all the
carbon, aggregated with a tiny part of all the oxygen, etc. Within the terms
of the mechanism thought experiment, none of the innumerably many possible
sets of concepts we might use to discriminate and relate objects can be
privileged over any other, and the choice between them will be arbitrary, or a
matter of subjective or pragmatic interest.
Hegel puts the point by saying, of the ‘mechanical object,’
that
the determinatenesses ... that it has in
itself, do indeed belong to it, but the form that constitutes their
difference and combines them into a unity is an external [äußerliche],
indifferent one. (WL 6:412/713)
Similarly, ‘the object’ has the
‘notion’ ‘as subjective’ or ‘outside itself (außer ihm)’ and all
‘determinateness is imposed from without (alle Bestimmtheit ist als eine
äußerlich gesetzte)’ (§195; see also WL 6:440/736). In a sense, then, any
given object lacks certain features and has others; there are
‘determinatenesses’ which ‘do indeed belong to it.’ But this is so only on the
basis of a concept which picks out the object in question—what Hegel here
calls the object’s ‘form’ or ‘notion’ (Begriff). And under the
conditions imposed by the mechanism thought experiment, the choice among
these will be arbitrary. That is, the concepts by which objects are
individuated—their ‘notions’—are a matter of indifference, merely ‘external’
to the matter at hand, or merely determined by ‘subjective’
interest.
The question is, however, why should any of this be a
problem? Why shouldn’t precisely the independence of mechanistic
accounts from whatever individuating concepts we happen to favor be a hallmark
of mechanism’s superior explanatory legitimacy? Hegel himself concedes that
this does seem a superiority if mechanism is contrasted with traditional forms
of ‘external purposiveness’ explanation, according to which different natural
beings all have a place and a purpose within the whole of reality, usually for
the sake of human beings—with the idea, for example, of explaining the cork
tree in terms of its relation to
wine-making.9
Viewed in that light, the arbitrariness mechanism introduces ‘gives the
consciousness of infinite freedom as compared with teleology, which sets up
for something absolute what is trivial and even contemptible in its content’
(WL 6:440/736). So why complain about external or subjective ‘notions’?
To see why, we must consider the constraints the thought
experiment will place on any attempt to ground or explain the distinction
between description and explanation itself. If mechanism alone is explanatory,
then any object to be explained is merely an aggregate, and cannot change in
ways which require explanation in terms of that very particular whole. In
Hegel’s terms, the mechanical object ‘has the determinateness of its totality
outside it in other objects’ (WL 6:412/713). To explain, then, we will have to
recharacterize our object in terms of its dependence on its parts or its
relations with other objects within a larger whole system. But now how
specifically shall we break our object into parts? And to which other objects
shall we relate it? Obviously there will be innumerably many ways of doing
both, and not all of these promise to explain anything. Say the explanandum is
the process of digestion in my cat’s stomach. Clearly there are innumerably
many ways we can describe her relations to many other objects without hitting
on anything remotely explanatory: we can describe her precise distance from
the Golden Gate Bridge, from Saturn, etc. We could similarly analyze her into
cube-shaped parts as divided by innumerably many arbitrary and imaginary
coordinate systems without making any contribution toward explaining. Hegel’s
is not an epistemological worry, namely, that we cannot know which of
the innumerably many possibilities can explain. The worry is that the total
mechanism hypothesis—if taken seriously—would undercut any possibility of a
genuine distinction between those which contribute to explaining and those
which do not. For the thought experiment constrains us to hold that every
way of discriminating the parts of my cat, and every way of
relating my cat or the parts of my cat to other objects within some larger
system—all of these are equally arbitrary, or equally a matter
of subjective preference. No matter what parts we distinguish, each of these
would have to be itself merely an aggregate. No matter what larger system
distinguish, all its parts would have to be external to one another,
explainable without essential reference to that particular whole system and
its other parts. If no way of redescribing can be privileged over or better
than any other, and all are equally arbitrary or a matter of subjective
preference, then there can be no distinction between those which explain and
those which merely describe. In Hegel’s terms, each account ‘assigns for each
determination of the object that of another object; but this other is
likewise indifferent’ (WL 6:412/713; emphasis mine).
Note that this is not the complaint—sometimes mistakenly
attributed to Hegel—that mechanism cannot explain because it cannot reach the
end of the infinite series it would need to complete before explaining the
totality of absolutely everything, and thereby first yielding a complete
explanation of anything in
particular.10
Hegel’s point is rather this: even imagining the completion an infinite ideal
mechanistic inquiry—even if this ideal project were possible to
complete—still this would do nothing to improve matters with respect to
grounding the notion of explanation itself, or distinguishing between
explanation and description. In this respect, inquiry might just as well ‘halt
and be satisfied at any point at will’ (WL 6:412/713). To complete in
isolation an infinite mechanistic inquiry would be to redescribe the
explanandum in relation to everything throughout the universe in every
possible way, down to the finest possible detail. But more information does
not always contribute to explanation; on the contrary, the problem is
precisely that so many possible ways of breaking things down and relating them
have no explanatory relevance. To distinguish explanation and description
would be to find some way single out some part of this infinite information,
screening out the vast majority of it. But even the imaged completeness of
infinite descriptive information would make no contribution toward such a
distinction. In Hegel’s terms, the mechanistic ‘progression to infinite’ aims
only at an infinite aggregation of everything, a ‘universe’ in the sense of a
‘totality’ characterized by ‘indeterminate individuality,’ (WL 6:412/713) or a
‘totality indifferent to determinateness’ (WL 6:429/727). Even if it were
achieved, this goal would still not include any distinction within the whole
of those determinate relevant factors which can actually explain anything in
particular.
The mechanism thought experiment is doomed to fail, then,
because if mechanistic explanation alone were legitimate, then all
‘notions’—that is, all ways of discriminating individuals and relating them to
others—would be equally fit to explain. And that is just to say that there
could not be any distinction between explanation and description, and so no
genuine notion of explanation at all. Or, within these confines, ‘the
explanation of the determination of an object and the progressive
determining of the object made for the purpose of explanation, is only an
empty word’ (WL
6:413/713-4).11
3. The Problem of Laws, and Why We Cannot Distinguish Explanations in Terms of
their Form
This general case is so abstract, of course, that it seems to
leave standing any number of specific ways of trying to account for the
distinction between explanation and description. Hegel himself proceeds to
consider several such specific attempts, and his responses clarify his general
reasons for thinking that no such proposal can succeed within the constraints
of the mechanism thought experiment.
One such proposal is that explanations explain, rather than
merely describe, in virtue of identifying general natural laws connecting
causes of a particular sort to effects of the sort to be
explained.12
The problem is, however, that there are innumerably many ways to assign
individuals to general classes, and there can be true generalizations
connecting such classes which nonetheless lack any law-like force or
necessity, and so lack any explanatory power. It is worth reaching back to the
(1807) Phenomenology for some humorous examples: ‘“it always rains when
we have our annual fair” says the dealer; “and every time, too,” says the
housewife, “when I am drying my washing”’ (PG 3:241/193). These
generalizations might be true—by some remarkable coincidence it might rain
every day that woman dries her laundry for her entire life. And describing in
such terms may best address her subjective interests. Still, the fact that she
is drying her laundry would never explain why it rains. The problem,
then, is how to distinguish between a true law and a non-explanatory
generalization, or—in Hegel’s terms—between a ‘law’ (Gesetz) and a mere
‘formal uniformity’ (Gleichförmigkeit) which ‘is indeed a rule
(Regel), but not a law (Gesetz)’ (WL
6:427/725).13
To draw this distinction, we would need some way to distinguish
those concepts which are fit to state genuine explanatory laws from the vast
majority of the possible ways of distinguishing individuals of a certain
general kind or class, which are not so fit—including, presumably, the concept
wash-day. But within the bounds of the mechanism thought experiment,
the problem of merely external notions will prevent doing so. Under these
conditions, all such concepts would be equally ‘external,’ or
simply different arbitrary ways we have of describing the world based on our
merely subjective interests. In Hegel’s terms, under these conditions, for the
object cited as cause under a proposed law, ‘its being cause is for it
something contingent’ (WL
6:415/715).14
In sum, the total mechanism hypothesis undermines not only the distinction
between explanation and description, but also the distinction between laws and
generalizations; thus there can be no question of drawing on the latter to
resolve the difficulties concerning the former.
This point concerning laws in particular should make clear that
Hegel’s worry about merely external notions provides him with general
considerations which cut against many more specific proposals than just those
he explicitly considers. For example, consider the proposal that explanations
are distinguished by their predictive power. The problem is, any
generalization which is universally true without exception would provide a
perfectly good basis for prediction. Since not all such true generalizations
are explanatory, predictive power cannot itself distinguish
explanation.15
And Hegel provides general reasons to doubt matters can be improved by adding
restrictions on the form explanations must take. For the proposal that
explanation is distinguished by the inclusion of something with the form of a
general law suffers not from a defect of form but of
content—specifically it cannot help to distinguish those specific
concepts suitable to state genuine explanatory
laws.16
It is another matter entirely, however, when we come to
proposals which distinguish explanation, not in terms of the form of
individual explanations, but in terms of some global formal standard. For
example, one might propose that explanations and/or laws are distinguished in
that they fit into the total theoretical system which best combines overall
simplicity with explanatory power. On such an account, what explains some
explanandum is not fixed within its locale; it is fixed globally in terms of
the best total theoretical system. This sort of proposal is less of a
challenge to Hegel’s desired conclusion, and more an illustration of it—or at
least an initial step toward it. For this proposal links explanatory status
and/or lawhood to what is supposed to be the goal of the overall
endeavor of inquiry into nature—for example, the best balance of maximum
simplicity and explanatory
power.17
But what is the status of this goal? If it is just an arbitrary subjective or
pragmatic interest that we happen to have, then this sort of proposal would
make the distinction between explanation and description relative to our
subjective interests; this would not account for, but rather undermine, the
objective notion of explanation. So such proposals must require that this goal
is instead a sort of objective aim constitutive of scientific inquiry itself;
that is, scientific inquiry will have to be a process which is intrinsically
organized by a goal or purpose. There will now be no arbitrariness when it
comes specifically to explaining any particular moment of this larger process;
each scientific experiment or revision of theory would be best explained in
teleological terms, in terms of the objective goals of scientific inquiry
itself (even if the individual researchers in question did not explicitly
think of their project in just such terms). And from here we might expand to a
general account of the distinctions between explanation and description, law
and generalization. For instance, we might then say that ‘it always rains when
I dry my washing’ could not be a law because classifying it as such within a
total theoretical system—alongside ‘F=ma’, etc.—would gain absurdly little
power at significant cost of simplicity. I’ll return below to compare this
sort of proposal with the interpretive options concerning Hegel’s own
solution. For now, the important point is how this proposal illustrates
Hegel’s general point: it is only insofar as we admit some form of
teleological explanation that we begin to get any sort of grip on the problem
of explanation; within the constraints of the total mechanism hypothesis the
problem remains irresolvable.
4. Forces At Work behind Natural Phenomena, and Why Such an Expansion of
Ontology Will Not Resolve the Problem
Hegel continues in ‘Mechanism’ to discuss the proposal that
explanation can be distinguished by appealing to powers or forces at work
behind empirical events—specifically, the ‘communication’ of ‘motion, heat,
magnetism, electricity and the like’ (WL 6:416/716), the interaction of
various fundamental forces, and especially the force of gravity. In looking at
his argument we must remain focused on the specific question at hand. The
question is, can appeal to fundamental forces such as gravity help, within the
constraints of total mechanism, to account for the distinction between
explanation and mere description? We must not confuse this with another
question, namely, can fundamental forces such as gravity explain any natural
phenomena? There can be no question here of resolving the traditional disputes
concerning Hegel’s answer to this second question, but it is worth noting the
‘Mechanism’ section in the Logic itself appears to suggest an
affirmative answer. In particular, this section concludes with discussion of
the law of gravity, governing the motion of matter around a ‘relative center’
and of all matter around an ‘absolute center’ (§198; WL 6:423ff/721ff). Hegel
claims that this is indeed a ‘law’ as opposed to mere ‘rule’ or generalization
(WL 6:427/725). This is perfectly in keeping with the Philosophy of
Nature, which portrays the scientific endeavor generally as ‘directed to a
knowledge of forces’ and ‘laws’ (§246). And, in particular, ‘gravitation is
the true and determinate notion of material corporeality’ (§269). To
apply the law of gravity in an account of the motion of matter around a center
is not merely to apply an external characterization, but a ‘notion’
(Begriff)—it is, in short,
explanatory.18
But Hegel’s focus in the Logic is not on the second
question, above, but the first: how are we to distinguish explanation from
mere description? It is one thing to say that accounts in terms of the law of
gravity are explanatory; the philosophical problem Hegel pursues in the
Logic is, why? And Hegel argues that appeal to forces cannot
help resolve this sort of philosophical question within the constraints of the
mechanism thought experiment. The specific arguments Hegel offers in the
‘Mechanism’ section reach back to the earlier second major part of the
Logic, the ‘Doctrine of Essence,’ which considers various philosophical
proposals for treating ordinary objects as the ‘reflection’ of underlying
essences. He draws upon in particular a dilemma posed by two ‘Remarks’
concerning explanation in the WL discussion of ‘Ground’ (Grund),
specifically in the sense of ‘ground’ or ‘reason’ demanded by the principle of
sufficient reason (WL 6:82/446).
On the first horn of the dilemma we find accounts in which the
appeal to forces is not meant to expand our ontology but rather to distinguish
a special general type or form of redescription of events; thus Hegel
classifies such proposals as ways of appealing to ‘formal ground’ (WL
6:96ff./456ff.). Here we meet an even broader formulation of the problem
discussed above concerning laws: to redescribe, even in terms of universally
true generalizations, is not necessarily to explain. If describing events in
terms of gravity were distinguished only in that it is a way of
classifying an explanandum together with other instances in which masses
accelerate toward one another, or subsuming it under a mathematical
generalization about such cases, then there would be no reason to think this
truly explains
anything.19
Hegel’s complaints about Newton tend to focus on this sort of worry: Within
the terms of Newton’s theory, there can be no account for why his own laws
should be explanatory, rather than just redescriptions of the phenomena. This
appeal to gravity is not objectionable because, as Leibniz suggests, it is
‘occult’; it is objectionable but because it is simply ‘too familiar’ (WL
6:99/459).
On the second horn of the dilemma we find the proposal that
appeal to fundamental forces expands our ontology by introducing something
independent of the events to be explained: a ‘real ground’ (WL
6:102ff./461ff.) responsible for producing, determining, or necessitating
events. Explanation could then be distinguished in a very different way: not
in virtue of being a special type or form of expression of the same sort of
fact expressed by true descriptions of the explanandum, but in virtue of
expressing the facts about something else, about the true forces or powers at
work behind the scenes. But what is the relationship supposed to be between
independent ground and explanandum? That is, what is the relationship in
virtue of which the latter is supposed to be explained? This cannot be, Hegel
insists, just another ordinary mechanistic relationship. The force of gravity
would then be, as it were, just another billiard ball on the table, colliding
with those billiard balls we can see and so explaining their motion. As Hegel
puts it in the Philosophy of Nature, the temptation is to ‘give a
physical meaning of independent forces’ (§270) to the laws of motion.
But clearly this sort of answer cannot help to ground the distinction between
explanation and description. If forces themselves were really supposed to be
just more of the same mechanical objects, just a few more billiard balls on
the table, then the expansion of ontology would have achieved nothing new, and
we would be returned to the initial problem: forces themselves would
themselves have to be merely aggregates, indifferent to any particular
characterization—any particular way of breaking them down into parts and
relating them to others—and so unable to help resolve the problem concerning
explanation.20
Within the specific limits of the total mechanism hypothesis,
however, there is no alternative way to approach the question of the
relationship between real ground and explanandum in virtue of which the latter
is supposed to be produced, determined, necessitated, etc. In effect, we are
left only with philosophical terms which suggest explanatory power,
such as ‘real ground.’ But the term ‘ground’ itself can do nothing to show
that there is some way to distinguish what really is the ground, or what
explains: ‘the real ground does not itself indicate which of the manifold
determinations ought to be taken as essential’ (WL 6:107/465). Alternatively,
reaching back to the Phenomenology, we might also say that an essential
force is supposed to ‘necessitate’ the explanandum. But when we accord an
independent existence to those forces, we simultaneously undercut our ability
to give this claim any content; thus we discover that ‘necessity’—like
‘explanation’ itself—‘has shown itself to be only an empty word’ (PG
3:122/93).
Again, Hegel’s complaint is not that mechanism could never
yield perfectly or ultimately complete explanation, because there will always
be an infinitely recurring gap between any ‘real ground’ and the explanandum
from which it is supposed to be distinct; Hegel is not arguing that mechanism
cannot explain, and he does not judge mechanism in terms of a questionable
ideal of perfectly complete or total
explanation.21
Rather: mechanism itself must draw on the idea that there is some distinction
between explaining and describing, and total mechanism would prevent any
account of that distinction, including any ‘real ground’ account. These
general considerations would apply similarly beyond the examples of forces
which Hegel considers—for example, to the proposal that natural phenomena have
a ‘real ground’ in laws which are themselves relationships between real
universals.22
Finally, this general problem of the ‘real ground’ is itself distinct from
epistemological worries about the possibility of explanatory knowledge, and of
any premises about the limits of our
knowledge.23
5. Recapping and Evaluating the Argument
Our original question above was this: what is the meaning of
Hegel’s claim about mechanism? Not, we have seen, that mechanistic accounts
offer a way of describing or classifying the world which is untrue, partially
true, or limited. For Hegel does not treat mechanism as a form of description
at all; he investigates mechanism’s explanatory purport. Nor is Hegel’s claim
that all mechanistic accounts are incomplete and so not explanatory. Hegel’s
claim is rather that mechanism cannot be the only legitimate form of
explanation, because this would undercut any possibility of accounting for the
distinction between explanation and description. So mechanism is limited
because it cannot account for its own explanatory status. In Hegel’s unusual
terms, mechanism does not ‘posses truth in and for itself’ (WL 6:437/734). But
that does not mean its claim to explain is false. Ultimately Hegel wants to
show that mechanism does ‘posses truth,’ not ‘in and for itself’ but only (as
Hegel might say) in another: he wants to show that some form of
teleology is ‘the truth of mechanism’ (WL 6:437-8/735).
How does Hegel support this criticism of mechanism without
appealing either to empirical considerations or to mere assumptions about the
world? He does so by connecting Kant’s sense of mechanism with a problem
concerning merely ‘external’ ‘notions’ which creates general difficulties
concerning the distinction between explanation and description. On the one
hand, generally anti-realist proposals will attempt to distinguish explanation
as a special type or form of redescription of the explanandum, for instance,
one that provides general laws covering such cases. But the total mechanism
hypothesis would render arbitrary all the concepts in which such laws or
explanations might be stated, blocking such proposals. On the other hand,
generally realist proposals will claim that explanation is distinguished in
stating the facts about the distinct and independent ‘real ground’ at work
behind events. But introducing any sort of real ground as distinct and
independent of the explanandum inevitably blocks any substantial account of
the relationship in virtue of which anything is supposed to be explained. So
whichever way we turn, within the limits of the mechanism thought experiment,
we are bound to lose the distinction between explanation and description, and
so the notion of explanation
itself.24
It thus turns out that any attempt to take seriously the proposal that only
mechanism explains will inevitably undermine itself by collapsing the notion
of explanation needed to frame that very proposal.
This argument is surprising in several respects. It differs
from many accounts of Hegel’s argument, in that it draws neither on a
stringent standard concerning complete, total or perfect explanation, nor on
claims about specific types of phenomena (e.g. living beings, ourselves) which
are supposed to be mechanically
inexplicable.25
There is nothing especially unusual about the problems concerning explanation
which drive Hegel’s argument, but Hegel’s attempt to turn these problems to
the end of a criticism of mechanism and, ultimately, a defense of teleology is
certainly an unusual and ambitious endeavor.
How successful is Hegel? That will have to depend, first of
all, on the status of two crucial premises, namely: (i) that the distinction
between explanation and description is objective, not merely relative to
arbitrary or subjective interests; and (ii) that this distinction needs, and
can be given, a substantial philosophical account. That the total mechanism
hypothesis blocks such accounts is, given these premises, indeed good reason
to reject the hypothesis. Of course, like any philosophical argument, Hegel’s
mechanism argument cannot do everything. It succeeds at associating
philosophical costs with the total mechanism hypothesis, and suggesting
philosophical benefits to follow from the rejection of that hypothesis; but it
does not itself counter every possible argument that these costs are worth
paying and/or that these benefits are worth foregoing or perhaps not
forthcoming at all. In this respect Hegel’s treatment of mechanism essentially
depends on the surrounding arguments in the Logic. In particular, the
preceding sections of the Logic must contribute some way of driving up
the philosophical costs involved in simply rejecting the premises.
Furthermore, Hegel’s subsequent treatment of teleology needs to make the case
that philosophical benefits too valuable to ignore or overlook—for instance, a
superior account of the grounds of explanation itself—really do follow the
rejection of the total mechanism hypothesis. Hegel’s own premises will make
this a very tall order, and so far I’ve said nothing to show he can meet the
challenge, other than sketching above a possible Hegelian strategy concerning
the goal-directed nature of the process of scientific inquiry.
But the ties between Hegel’s mechanism argument and his broader
project, while diminishing the independence of that argument, also present an
important opportunity. In the final sections below, I’ll show how
investigation of these ties not only clarifies the character of the mechanism
argument, but also helps to illuminate Hegel’s broader philosophical project
in the Logic.
6. Why Explanation Cannot Be Inexplicable, and the Basic Commitment of the
Logic
Let’s begin with what I have distinguished as Hegel’s second
premise. Why think that the distinction between explanation and description
needs, and can be given, a substantial philosophical account? Why not hold
instead that this distinction is simply primitive, and so philosophically
inexplicable? Certain concepts, we might say, just are explanatory, fit for
stating natural laws, etc. Not because they correspond to special
ontologically distinct entities, though they might, but just because they are
so fit. After all, one might reasonably propose that no philosophy can account
for everything; if something must be primitive, why not
this?26
To see the response suggested by Hegel’s mechanism argument,
compare Kant’s account of the objectivity of experience. Why think that
objectivity is something for which we need a philosophical account? Why not
say instead that some of our representations simply capture the way things
really are and others simply do not, but that this distinction itself cannot
and need not be further explained? The answer is that this would render
utterly mysterious our own grasp of the distinction between objective and
subjective. We are on to the idea, for example, of a distinction between
objective and subjective time-order, regardless of how well or how poorly we
manage to sort this out in practice. And so we need an account of how the
distinction is fixed within our experience or empirical cognition; Kant
will famously argue that this requires a priori objectively valid
formal conditions of cognition, and that recognizing instead only empirical
‘laws of association’ would collapse the distinction between objective and
subjective
entirely.27
To refuse to engage such philosophical problems by saying that the distinction
between objective and subjective is primitive and philosophically inexplicable
would make necessary a special account of our own grasp of the objective as
opposed to the subjective. And this special account will have to be a form of
what Kant characterizes, in the famous February 1772 letter to Marcus Herz, as
a ‘deus ex machina’: it might be, for instance, a Platonic ‘previous
intuition of divinity,’ or Crusius’ appeal to ‘concepts that God implanted in
the human soul’ (a form of pre-established harmony between subject and
object). Kant responds that accepting such a ‘deus ex machina’ so close
to home, at the very heart of our experience or cognition of the world, would
mean we are willing to accept it anywhere. We could then justify pretty much
anything at all by viewing it as ‘implanted’ by God, encouraging ‘all sorts of
wild notions and every pious and speculative brainstorm’ (Ak. 10:131/C 134).
As Kant says of Crusius’ proposal in the Prolegomena, the problem is
the ‘lack of sure criteria to distinguish the genuine origin from the
spurious, since we never can know certainly what the spirit of truth or the
father of lies may have instilled into
us.’28
Now compare Hegel’s mechanism argument. The idea is that our
thinking about the world aims at explanation—we try to understand in the sense
of grasping the why of things. This means we are on to the distinction
between explanation and description, regardless of how well or poorly we are
able to sort it out in practice. We thus need an account of how that
distinction is fixed within our thinking about the world. Hegel wants
to argue that this requires the legitimacy of some form of teleological
explanation, and that recognizing instead only mechanism as legitimate would
collapse the distinction between explanation and description entirely.
What is the alternative to engaging this philosophical problem
concerning explanation? Hegel takes the alternative to be represented best by
an argument of Jacobi’s recounted near the beginning of the
Encyclopedia. Jacobi (Hegel says) claims that any finite and
determinate rational account of anything merely connects it to something else
finite and determinate, and so itself in need of explanation; such accounts
therefore can never truly explain. But we do seek for true explanations. We
must therefore have a prior understanding of the goal which we seek in trying
to explain: ‘God, or what is infinite and true’ which necessarily ‘lies
outside of the mechanical interconnection of this kind’ (§62A). Our
understanding of this goal cannot stem from the sort of thought or cognition
which seeks to explain or derive, by which the goal would merely be ‘perverted
into untruth’ or ‘transformed into something conditioned and mediated’ (§62).
We must instead have an ‘immediate knowledge
(unmittelbare Wissen) of God and the true,’
(§62A) specifically in the form of faith
(Glaube) (§63).
One can, then, refuse to engage the philosophical problem of
accounting for the distinction between explanation and description by making
that distinction primitive and so philosophically inexplicable. But there is a
price. Given that we do seek to explain things, we would have to possess some
special grasp of this inexplicable distinction—for we would have to have some
grasp of the goal we seek in trying to explain rather than merely describe.
This special grasp would have to be so transparent, deep, and certain that no
doubt could possibly arise as to whether it gets at the heart of the matter,
or reveals the essence of what it is to explain rather than a merely
describing explanation in an inessential manner. For this special grasp would
have to itself provide the standard relative to which all such doubts could
arise at all. We would need, in short, to appeal to immediate self-justifying
insight into the inexplicable distinction between explanation and
description—into something prior to, distinct from, and the foundation for all
explanatory thinking. And that, Hegel argues in his response to Jacobi, is too
high a price to pay. For it would make this most fundamental truth something
which in principle cannot be subject to any form of justification save the
apprehension or feeling of immediate
self-justification.29
As in Kant’s worries about the deus ex machina, the problem with this
concerns criteria: such ‘immediate knowledge’ can only be ‘subjective
knowing’; it must take a mere ‘factum of consciousness as the criterion
of truth’ (§71). And by this standard any ‘superstition or idolatry’ might
rightly be ‘proclaimed as truth’ (§72). If we were willing to allow that, then
why bother with philosophy? Philosophy, by contrast, ‘will not tolerate any
mere assurances or imagining’ (§77) and so must exclude appeals to forms of
immediate knowledge, such as ‘inspiration, revelation of the heart, a content
implanted in man by nature,’ (§63A) etc.
It would be well worth pursuing this argument at greater
length, for Jacobi himself might have more to say on behalf of his proposals,
or there might be some other promising defense of inexplicability. But for our
purposes what is crucial is to recognize how radically different Hegel’s
approach is. This is crucial because Hegel’s response to Jacobi highlights the
general appeal not only of a key premise of the mechanism argument, but also
of what is perhaps the central commitment of Hegel’s theoretical
philosophy. For Hegel generally begins his theoretical works—starting already
with the (1807) Phenomenology—by ruling out any foundational appeal to
immediate knowledge, including as well forms of ‘intellectual intuition’
proposed by Fichte and
Schelling.30
Hegel does not do so because he assumes that reality must be so thoroughly
unified that everything can be explained, as a whole, so that in principle
nothing could possibly be inexplicable. (Merely to assume this would be
question-begging in the extreme, and manifestly so in the face of Kant’s
arguments against the unrestricted application of the principle of
sufficient reason.) Hegel’s reason is rather this: If the most fundamental
truths were such as to admit only a merely subjective justification, then
there would be nothing to be gained by engaging in philosophy, or by
attempting philosophical derivations, demonstrations, or
justifications.31
If the project of philosophy is to make any sense at all, then, it must
renounce all foundational appeals to immediacy. Thus the WL begins by parting
ways with ‘those who begin, like a shot from a pistol, from their inner
revelation, from faith, intellectual intuition, etc., and who would be exempt
from method and logic’ (WL 5:65/67; Cf. PG 31/16). Philosophy, itself a
form of the ‘thinking consideration of objects,’ (§1) must attempt to do
without any ‘absolutes’ which are supposedly accessible by going outside
thought or explanatory thinking, or beyond that sort of cognition which aims
to understand or grasp the why. The proof, however, is in the pudding:
this procedure can be justified only insofar as Hegel can demonstrate
philosophical results without any illegitimate appeals to immediacy. Thus
there is a natural sense in which Hegel insists that his results must circle
back to justify his beginning (e.g. §17).
7. Implications of this Central Commitment Concerning the Mechanism Argument
and the Logic Project
This rejection of appeals to immediacy has, to begin with,
important implications concerning the character of Hegel’s mechanism argument
and its relationship to considerations introduced by his contemporaries. For
instance, this explains why Hegel cannot take what might seem an easier route,
and deny the total mechanism hypothesis on grounds that it leaves no room for
spontaneous, self-conscious subjects such as ourselves. (On grounds, that is,
that a complete conceptual scheme limited to mechanism alone would exclude any
place for anyone capable of actively applying that scheme in judging or
experiencing objects.) The problem is, any such argument would have to begin
with a form of supposedly immediate insight into our own spontaneous
subjectivity. It would require, in fact, something very like Fichte’s appeal
to ‘intellectual intuition’ as ‘immediate consciousness that I
act.’32
Aside from his general complaint about immediate knowledge, Hegel worries that
thus assuming of the spontaneous subject as an independently
authoritative standard governing forms of explanation of objects would
insurmountably divorce subject from object, specifically in the sense of
making their relation in knowledge and action
inexplicable.33
And it should now be clear why Hegel’s complaint cannot be that
mechanism fails to account in a perfectly complete manner for the totality of
everything. Many interpretations, perhaps most, boil down to some version of
this ‘incompleteness
complaint.’34
But this would amount to a criticism of mechanism only given the additional
premise that reality is the sort of unified totality which can and must
be completely and perfectly explained as a whole. And what can be the status
of that premise? The premise cannot be justified by consideration of
different forms of explanation if it must be in place already, from the
beginning, to provide the standard according to which mechanism is supposed to
fail. Such a premise could only be delivered by a supposedly immediate or
self-justifying insight into the unity and intelligibility of reality itself.
And this is precisely what Hegel rules out. Furthermore, Hegel’s discussion of
Jacobi shows that he is very much aware of the difficulty: an appeal to
immediate knowledge would be required to support an argument that, because
finite accounts are inevitably incomplete, true explanation would require
something which ‘lies outside of the mechanical interconnection of this kind’
(§62A). So attention to Hegel’s relation to the historical context should not
encourage us to read him as deploying a mechanism argument which mirrors
Jacobi—or other contemporaries (such as Fichte) who appeal to forms of
immediate knowledge or intellectual intuition. Hegel’s basic commitment
requires, as he correctly recognizes, a new argument which operates in a very
different manner.
And such an argument is just what we have found. In fact,
Hegel’s argument is nearly the precise opposite of an appeal to the total
unity of everything there is. Recognizing mechanism alone as explanatory,
Hegel argues, would make arbitrary or subjective all differences between
individuals, dissolving all reality away into a perfect seamless unity of
everything, a ‘totality indifferent to determinateness’ (WL 6:429/727). But
Hegel stresses—in the ‘Mechanism’ section and also in his various complaints
about traditional forms of monism—that such a totality would leave no way to
account for the distinction between explanation and description, no way to
grasp what it would be to explain anything in
particular.35
Thus we cannot coherently suppose that mechanism alone is explanatory. This
argument does not judge mechanism from a standpoint which we are assured is
higher, complete, infinite, unconditioned, etc. It judges only in terms of
mechanism’s own intrinsic claim to explain rather than merely describe;
Hegel finds that total mechanism would inevitably undercut this claim, even at
the imagined completion of infinite inquiry.
Finally, all this means that we can—and indeed must—move beyond
traditional interpretive approaches to Hegel’s overall argument strategy.
Traditional approaches tend to divide, over the issue of Hegel’s relationship
to Kant’s critical philosophy, into metaphysical and non-metaphysical
interpretations. What characterizes metaphysical interpretations is not so
much their reading of Hegel’s conclusions, but their insistence that Hegel’s
premises include an assumption of the possibility of complete knowledge of all
reality as an unconditioned whole, or of the total transparency of reality to
thought.36
Hegel is then supposed to read Kant through the lens of this assumption,
assimilating Kant’s comments about what God and the cosmos might be
like while ignoring Kant’s arguments against the possibility of theoretical
knowledge of such topics and against pre-critical metaphysics
generally.37
The result would be neither an internal critique nor a philosophically
promising argument, for to assume that we can basically know everything would
be to beg the question against Kant and (remarkably) against every single form
of skepticism ever entertained. Non-metaphysical interpretations reverse this
reading of Hegel’s relation to Kant. The idea is that Hegel agrees with Kant
that we cannot know that one or another fundamental sort of entity most
fundamentally exists and ultimately explains; though Hegel may occasionally
waver, his core project is supposed to avoid such metaphysical questions in
favor of reflection on only the general notions necessary for us to think of
any object at all, on the form of our knowledge, the conditions of the
possibility of any conceptual scheme,
etc.38
But the evidence of Hegel’s mechanism argument suggests a very
different way of understanding both his relationship to Kant and his basic
argument
strategy.39
To begin with, we have just seen that Hegel does not and cannot begin with the
assumptions concerning unity and total intelligibility which are attributed to
him by metaphysical interpretations, as these could only be an appeal to
immediate knowledge which Hegel rejects. Hegel insists instead that we
renounce all foundational appeal to immediacy and generally to what is
supposed to be an inherently authoritative standard governing thought or
cognition from outside their reach. Hegel takes himself to be agreeing
here with the basic insight behind Kant’s own critical turn, which Hegel
expresses like this: ‘all authority can receive validity only through thought’
(VGP
20:331/424).40
In Kant’s terms, ‘pure reason’ must be the ‘supreme court of justice for all
disputes’ (A740/B768).
The dispute between them turns largely on Kant’s limitation of
our knowledge to appearances. Kant takes explanatory thought, or ‘reason,’ to
aim implicitly at knowledge of the completely unconditioned—especially at
knowledge of the absolutely necessary being which would completely and
perfectly explain everything, because its ‘concept’ would contain ‘within
itself the “Because” to every “Why?”’
(A585/B613).41
Kant also holds that any such unconditioned object would violate the
conditions of the possibility of natural phenomena, or objects of empirical
cognition; anything in space, for example, is merely conditioned by its
parts.42
We seem compelled, then, to deny the possibility of the unconditioned which we
nonetheless implicitly seek insofar as we try to explain anything. The only
way to avoid self-contradiction is to distinguish the objects of our knowledge
from unknowable things-in-themselves, and thus make room for ‘a condition of
appearances which is outside the series of appearances,’ (A531/B559) and in
particular a necessary being ‘entirely outside the series of the world of
sense’
(A561/B589).43
But this is a conclusion which Hegel aims to challenge, and not
by assumption but by argument. Hegel asks: if our explanatory thinking seeks
the unconditioned, and the unconditioned cannot be cognized, then how do we
grasp this goal in order to seek it? If the goal is not merely to be a
subjective illusion of ours, then we would have to have some special
non-cognitive access to it via some form of immediate knowledge. This would
have to be something akin to a ‘reminiscence of the divine’ or some insight
‘that God implanted in the human soul’—precisely the ‘deus ex machina’
(Ak 10:131/C 134) Kant himself seeks to avoid. This criticism does not assume
that we can know or explain everything, only that we do seek to explain and so
must somehow grasp what it is we are thus seeking. Thus we can see how Hegel
aims, at least, to criticize Kant from within, arguing that Kant’s own
critical insight does not require but rather rules out Kant’s limitation of
our knowledge to
appearances.44
The moral Hegel draws is that, if we really want to see where
the critical refusal of immediacy leads us, then we must allow the
contradictions Kant uncovers to push us toward a different and better
understanding of cognition or explanatory thinking
itself.45
In particular, we must reject the idea that mechanism alone is legitimate, and
with it the insistence that everything in space must be merely an aggregate of
independent parts. And we must proceed in this manner to seek to show how the
distinction between explanation and description can be grasped, derived, or
justified within explanatory thinking itself. This does not mean that
we must have knowledge or cognition of precisely what Kant suggests might lie
beyond the reach of cognition: something ‘entirely outside the series of the
world of sense,’ (A561/B589) and something ‘the concept of which contains
within itself the “Because” to every “Why?”’ (A585/B613). As we have seen, the
mechanism argument does not criticize mechanism on the grounds that it fails
to account for absolutely everything in a perfectly complete manner. The idea
that such an unreachable standard or goal distinguishes explanation belongs
with the conclusion Hegel resists, namely, the limitation of our knowledge to
appearances. To avoid Kant’s conclusions Hegel must justify a new and
different conception of what distinguishes explanation and description. And
that means showing that the sort of thinking which seeks to derive or to
justify can ultimately arrive at an understanding of that in virtue of which
explanations truly explain, the ground, foundation or standard for all answers
to all why-questions—or, in short, of what Hegel calls ‘the absolute.’
This is a tall order, to be sure. And, again, the proof is in
the pudding: the only way Hegel’s procedure can be justified is by producing
results.46
There can be no question of arguing here that Hegel really succeeds. But it is
crucial that we cannot understand even what the project aims to be and to do
if we see it as limited in the ways suggested by traditional approaches. In
particular, the project is not limited in that it rests on mere assumptions
drawn from pre-critical metaphysics. It is rooted instead in a critical
commitment to avoid a foundational appeal to faith, intuition, or any
supposedly immediate knowledge beyond the limits of thought, or a court of
appeal higher than pure reason itself. But precisely in order to make good on
the resulting internal criticism of Kant’s critical philosophy, Hegel’s
project cannot be limited to merely non-metaphysical ambitions. This can be no
Kantian examination of the conceptual conditions of our experience or
empirical knowledge. Nor can this be a series of negative or deflationary
arguments that the traditional metaphysical worries about what lies beyond our
conceptual scheme (or form of life, normative practices, etc.) are
unintelligible and so idle. To succeed and to justify his starting point,
Hegel needs an ambitious and positive attempt to justify or derive an account
that which most fundamentally exists, specifically in the sense of that which
truly grounds all explanation in the objective sense—an account of ‘the
absolute.’
8. Questions and Options Concerning the Grounds of the Objective Notion of
Explanation and the Conclusions of the Logic
What can the evidence of the mechanism argument teach us about
how this ambitious attempt plays itself out in the Logic? To begin
with, consider Hegel’s other crucial premise—namely, that there really is an
objective distinction between explanation and description. Why think so? Why
not hold instead that there is no explanation in the objective sense, only
innumerably many descriptions which address to different degrees the various
subjective interests we might have? This premise is, I think, one of the few
cases where common-sense might actually be on Hegel’s side. For it does not
seem that the truth about what really explains what should vary with changes
in our arbitrary subjective or pragmatic interests.
But an appeal to common-sense (which would be another appeal to
supposedly immediate knowledge) is not good enough for
Hegel.47
Nor should it be, for there might well be good philosophical reasons to think
that the price involved in rejecting the objective notion of explanation must
be paid, or even that it is not so costly as it first appears. This presents
problems, for without that notion Hegel’s mechanism argument can do nothing to
bolster his broader case against the idea that all possible individuating
concepts could be equally arbitrary, or merely a matter of subjective
preference. So the Logic should have more, aside from the contents of
the ‘Mechanism’ section, by way of argument that denying the objective notion
of explanation in order to insist on the subjectivity of all concepts involves
unacceptable philosophical costs. The question is, how does Hegel so argue?
One possibility looks like this: if all concepts are arbitrary or subjective
then the world is, in itself, independent of all concepts or universals; but
without the latter there is nothing to provide the persistence conditions for
individual objects; and (Hegel would like to argue) we simply cannot get a
real grasp on the idea of such a world without determinate persisting objects,
where there is no change but only ‘passing-over into another’ (Übergehen in
Anderes), no ‘essence’ but only
‘being.’48
But I do not mean to defend this argument here, or to argue that my reading of
Hegel’s mechanism argument resolves at once all questions about the
Logic. The point is rather to use the evidence of the ‘Mechanism’
section to frame the specific questions which can narrow the interpretive
options concerning the Logic’s extended argument.
Similarly, Hegel’s mechanism argument suggests a series of
questions concerning the conclusions of the Logic as a whole. Q1: What
form(s) of teleological explanation will Hegel defend? Q2: How can he make
sense of the explanatory legitimacy of teleological explanation, alongside
mechanism, if these both claim to explain (in the objective sense) and not
merely to describe or classify? Q3: How can such teleology provide an
alternative to the idea that all individuating concepts are equally arbitrary
or subjective? Q4: And how can it account for or ground the distinction
between explanation and description?
I will limit myself here to sketching two very different
interpretive approaches to these questions. The first, though I do not
advocate it, is more straightforward. The basic idea is that removing the
restriction to mechanism brings into view naturally and intrinsically unified
wholes, paradigmatically living beings. The presence of the parts of such
living beings could be explained specifically in terms of their roles or
functions in the survival and reproduction of individual organisms of a
specific biological species (Q1). Such explanation could be argued to be
compatible with mechanism in virtue accounting for something different,
namely, the organization of individual organisms within the larger
whole species (Q2). And the concepts of these biological species-kinds would
not be arbitrary, subjective or externally imposed; they would be privileged
as true or intrinsic ‘notions’ and of explanatory relevance. Not because they
accord with some formal standard, or because they capture the truth about
something else which is independent of or beyond the natural phenomena. True
notions would rather be present in the natural phenomena, specifically in the
form of the active organizing principles which form nature into the repeating
patterns of different biological species (Q4). A notion in this sense would
not be merely one predicate among many which could be attributed to a logical
subject; it would be the very foundation of there being a persisting and
determinate logical subject which might bear such predicates (Q3). In sum, we
might thus read Hegel as arguing for a realist theory of immanent universals
or substantial forms, reminiscent of
Aristotle.49
I myself favor an interpretive approach according to which
Hegel’s discussions of biology are meant not as a solution but as an initial
step toward a very different sort of
view.50
For I think Hegel ultimately argues that there is only one kind whose notion
is truly intrinsic or internal. This is the kind to which we ourselves belong:
Geist (‘mind’ or ‘spirit’). Geist is supposed to be
distinguished in being uniquely self-forming: we are fundamentally shaped by
self-conscious conflict, debate and dispute about who or what we are, who or
what we should be, and how we should understand the world around us. (This
involves counter-intuitive claims which will be difficult to justify or even
to reconcile: in particular, our development generally is supposed to be
guided in by objective and intrinsic goals—and yet also, somehow, a
self-formation, even free.
51)
To see the impact of this proposal on questions Q1-4, consider again the
teleological or goal-directed account of scientific inquiry sketched above
(section 3); ultimately this process too is simply part of the overall
development of Geist. On such an account, individual activities such as
conducting experiments and proposing new theories can be best explained in
terms of the objective goal or goals of scientific inquiry itself (Q1). This
form of teleological explanation too might be argued to be compatible with
mechanism in virtue of explaining something else, in this case the
organization of our activities within the larger whole of theoretical
inquiry (Q2). Certain natural kind concepts would then be privileged as
internal ‘notions’ (Q3) and as explanatory (Q4). But in contrast with the
first interpretive option above, this would not be because of any supposed
correspondence with an independent, underlying and pre-determined organizing
structure inherent in nature. It would rather be because of the place of such
notions in the total theoretical system which best meets the objective goals
of the process of scientific inquiry, or (more generally) of the development
of
Geist.52
It is worth briefly noting some interpretive advantages of this
last proposal. First, it can make sense of Hegel’s claims that that teleology
is ‘the truth of mechanism’ (WL 6:437-8/735), and also that Geist in
particular is ‘the truth of nature’ (§389) as a whole. For example, gravity
would be privileged as the truly explanatory ‘notion’ of matter (§269)
because of the teleological goals of Geist, and biological species
concepts would be privileged for the same reason. We might also approach in
these terms Hegel’s denials that natural beings generally (and living
beings in particular) are or can be perfectly organized into rational systems,
and his insistence on the ‘boundless and unchecked contingency’ of nature
(§248A).53
Second, this proposal amounts to a robust but unusual form of
philosophical idealism. It is unusual in that it would not require that
everything is (or is constructed from) mind, consciousness, perceptions, or
the like; the existence of matter and the blackness of my cat, for example,
needn’t be dependent on
Geist.54
But it is nonetheless a substantial philosophical idealism with plenty of
counter-intuitive implications. In particular, the concepts which pick out
genuine natural kinds and the generalizations which count as explanatory
natural laws would depend on Geist or ‘mind’—not on merely arbitrary or
subjective preferences, of course, but on the objective goals of the
development of Geist. It is in terms of this latter claim that we might
approach Hegel’s idea that knowledge of the absolute—knowledge of that which
most fundamentally exists, specifically in the sense of that in virtue of
which true explanations truly explain—is actually a form of self-knowledge (WL
6:469/760).
Third, this proposal would amount to a significant departure
from traditional forms of monism. Granted, Geist is supposed to be ‘the
truth of nature,’ and there can be only one Geist, including any and
all who might relate to others in a self-conscious manner, or a manner which
raises fundamental questions about themselves and the world around them. But
this is not a unity that is assumed from the beginning; it is supposed to be
derived or justified by Hegel’s argument concerning
explanation.55
And this is most definitely not a seamless unity: Geist is what
it is only insofar as it is driven by self-conscious conflict, debate, and
disagreement. Thus we might approach Hegel’s insistence that his idealism—with
its emphasis on ‘negation,’ ‘activity,’ and ‘self-consciousness’—is not a
different way of coming to traditional conclusions, or of rearranging some
details in a traditional Weltvorstellung or
representation of the world. It rather marks a significant philosophical
departure from and critique of traditional metaphysical systems, including not
only Aristotle’s but Spinoza’s as
well.56
There can of course be no question of interpretive or
philosophical defense here of these final suggestions or proposals. But the
philosophical argument in the ‘Mechanism’ does, at least, highlight the
central commitment of the Logic, point out the way to overcome the
inadequacy of non-metaphysical and metaphysical approaches to that work, and
raise specific questions which narrow the options concerning its overall
argument and conclusions. Thus attention to Hegel’s focus on problems
concerning explanation, especially as these drive his argument against total
mechanism, allows us to see how the Logic might really be precisely
what Hegel means it to be: it begins with non-question-begging premises which
do not require any special appeal to immediacy; it proceeds by means of
ambitious and constructive philosophical arguments; and it aims (at least) to
reach thereby substantial and controversial philosophical conclusions about
‘the
absolute.’57
James Kreines
Department
of Philosophy
Yale University
PO Box 208306
New Haven, CT
06520
USA
james.kreines@yale.edu
Primary Texts / Abbreviations
HEGEL
#:# Werke in
zwanzig Bände. Edited by E. Moldenhauer und K. Michel, 20 Vol.,
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970-1. Except in the case of the Encyclopedia, I
cite with volume:page from this edition, followed by the page number in
the English translation listed below. I have altered translations where
necessary.
§ Enzyklopädie
der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830) = Werke vol. 8-10.
Cited by section number. ‘A’ indicates Hegel’s remarks, ‘Z’ indicates
the Zusätze.
For translations, see EL and:
Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind. Translated by W. Wallace and A. V.
Miller. New York: Oxford University Press, 1971.
Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature. Translated by W. Wallace and A. V.
Miller. New York: Oxford University Press, 1970.
EL Die
Wissenschaft der Logik, Erster Teil, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen
Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830) = Werke vol. 8.
Hegel’s Logic.
Encyclopaedia Logic, trans. TF Geraets, HS Harris, and WA Suchting,
Hackett Publishing Co, 1991.
PG Phänomenologie des Geistes
= Werke vol. 3.
Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by A.V. Miller.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.
VGP Vorlesengen
über die Geschichte der Philosophie = Werke vol. 18-20.
Lectures on the History of Philosophy. Translated by E. S.
Haldane and Frances H. Simson. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1995.
Cited by volume (1-3) and page.
WL Wissenschaft
der Logik = Werke vol. 5-6.
Hegel’s Science of Logic. Translated by A.V. Miller. London: George
Allen & Unwin, 1969.
KANT
Ak. Immanuel
Kants Schriften. Ausgabe der königlich preußischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1902-). Aside from the Kritik der
reinen Vernunft, all citations use volume:page from this
edition. For translations, see below. Translations altered where
necessary.
A/B Kritik der
reinen Vernunft. Ed. R. Schmidt. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1956.
Critique of
Pure Reason. Translated by Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge, 1998.
C
Correspondence. ed. Arnulf Zweig. New York: Cambridge University Press,
1999
KU
Critique of Judgment. Translated by Guyer and Mathews.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
P Prolegomena
to Any Future Metaphysics. Translated by Lewis White Beck. Indianapolis,
IN: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1950.
Other Works Cited
Allison, H. E. 1991. Kant’s antinomy
of teleological judgment. Southern Journal of Philosophy 30
(Supplement): 25-42.
Beck, L. W. 1989. ‘Two Ways of
Reading Kant’s Letter to Herz: Comments on Carl’ in Kant's Transcendental
Deductions. Ed. E. Förster. Stanford, California: Stanford University
Press.
Beiser, F.C. 1995. Hegel, a
non-metaphysician? A polemic, Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain
32.
Bole, T. and Stevens J. M. 1985. Why
Hegel at All? Philosophical Topics 13: 113-122.
Carl, W. 1989. ‘Kant’s First Drafts
of the Deduction of the Categories’ in Kant's Transcendental
Deductions. Ed. E. Förster. Stanford, California: Stanford University
Press.
DeVries, W. 1991. The dialectic of
teleology. Philosophical Topics 19: 51-70.
Dretske, F. 1977. “Laws of Nature”,
Philosophy of Science, 44: 248-268.
Düsing, K. 1990.
Naturteleologie und Metaphysik bei Kant und Hegel. In: Hegel und die Kritik
der Urteilskraft, Hrsg. von H.-F. Fulda und R.-P. Horstmann.
Stuttgart. 139-157.
Earman, J. 1978, “The Universality of
Laws”, Philosophy of Science, 45: 173-181.
Fichte, J.G.
1845-6. Fichtes sämtliche Werke. Ed. I. H. Fichte. Berlin:
Veit.
Fichte, J.G. 1982.
The Science of Knowledge. Trans. Peter Heath
and John Lachs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Forster, M. 1998. Hegel’s idea of
a Phenomenology of Spirit. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Ginsborg, H. 2001. Kant on
Understanding Organisms as Natural Purposes. In Kant and the Sciences,
ed. Eric Watkins. New York: Oxford University Press.
Guyer, P. 1993. Thought and being:
Hegel’s critique of Kant’s theoretical philosophy in The Cambridge
companion to Hegel, ed. Frederick Beiser. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Hartmann, K. 1976a. ‘Die ontologische
Option’ in Die ontologische Option, ed. K. Hartmann, Berlin-New York:
de Gruyter.
Hartmann, K. 1976b. Hegel: a
non-metaphysial view. In Hegel: a collection of critical essays, ed.
A. MacIntyre. Notre Dame: Notre Dame
Press.
Horstmann, R. P.
1984. Ontologie Und Relationen : Hegel, Bradley, Russell Und Die
Kontroverse Uber Interne Und Externe Beziehungen. Konigstein/Ts.:
Athenaum : Hain.
Horstmann, R. P. 1990. Wahrheit aus
dem Begriff. Eine Einführung in Hegel, Frankfurt/M.
Horstmann, R. P. 1991. Die Grenzen
der Vernunft. Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen und Motiven des Deutschen
Idealismus, Frankfurt am Main.
Inwood, M. 1983. Hegel.
London: Routledge.
Kitcher, P. 1986. Projecting the
order of nature. In Kant’s philosophy of physical science, ed. R.E.
Butts. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Kreines, J. (unpublished manuscript),
‘Accounting for the Inexplicability of Kant’s Naturzweck: Kant on
Teleology and Biological Explanation’.
Kolb, Daniel C. 1988. Matter and
mechanism in Kant’s critical system. Idealistic Studies 18: 123-144
Lewis, D. 1999. ‘New Work for a
Theory of Universals’ In: Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology: Volume 2.
Cambridge, Cambridge Univ. Press.
Loewer, B., 1996, ‘Humean
Supervenience’, Philosophical Topics, 24: 101-126.
McLaughlin, P. 1990. Kant’s critique
of teleology in biological explanation. Lewiston: Edwin Mellen
Press.
Petry, M. J.
1978. ‘Introduction’ to Hegels Philosophie des
subjektiven Geistes. Edited and translated by M. J. Petry. 3 vol.
Boston: Doderecht, 1978.
Pinkard, T. 1988. Hegel’s
dialectic. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Pippin, R. 1989. Hegel’s
idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pippin, R. 1997.
Hegel, freedom, the will. In G. W. F.
Hegel: Philosophie des Rechts, ed. L. Siep. Berlin: Akadamie
Verlag.
Pippin, R. 2000. ‘Fichte's Alleged
One-Sided, Subjective, Psychological Idealism,’ in The Reception of Kant's
Critical Philosophy. Ed. Sally Sedgwick, Cambridge University
Press.
Quine, W. V. O. 1969. Natural kinds.
In Ontological relativity and other essays. Columbia University Press,
New York, NY.
Railton, P. 1981. Probabilty,
explanation, and information. Synthese 48: 233-56.
Salmon, W. 1984. Scientific
explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Siep, L. 1991. Hegel’s Idea of a
Conceptual Scheme. Review Discussion of R. Pippin, Hegel’s Idealism. Inquiry,
vol. 34, 63-76.
Siep, L. 2000. Der Weg der
Phänomenologie des Geistes. Ein einführender Kommentar zu Hegels
‘Differenzschrift’ und ‘Phänomenologie des Geistes’, Frankfurt:
Suhrkamp.
Stern, Robert. 1990. Hegel, Kant
and the Structure of the Object. London ; New York:
Routledge.
Strawson, P. F. 1966. The bounds
of sense. London: Methuen.
Taylor, C. 1975. Hegel.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
van Frassen, B. 1980. The
scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
van Lunteren, F. H. 1986. Hegel and
Gravitation. In: Horstmann, R. P. and Petry, M. J. (eds):
Hegels Philosophie der Natur, Stuttgart: Ernst Klett
Verlag.
Ward, B., 2002, “Humeanism without
Humean supervenience: A projectivist account of laws and possibilities”,
Philosophical Studies,107: 191-218.
Watkins, E. 2001. ‘The “Critical
Turn”: Kant and Herz from 1770 to 1772’ in Proceedings of the Ninth
International Kant Congress. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Westphal, K. R. 2000. ‘Kant, Hegel,
and the Fate of “the” Intuitive Intellect’ in the Reception of Kant’s
Critical Philosophy. (ed) Sedgwick, Sally. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ
Press.
Wolff, M. 1991. Eine Skizze zur
Auflösung des Leib-Seele-Problems. In Psychologie und
Anthropologie oder Philosophie des Geistes, eds. F. Hespe and B.
Tuschling. Stuttgart: Friedrich Frommann Verlag.
NOTES
1
My main focus is the (1812-16) Wissenschaft der
Logik (WL), though I will draw heavily upon the first part of
Hegel’s Encyclopedia, which also bears that name (EL). Both contain a
‘Mechanism’ section, and the complaint about mechanism is similar in both. I
will also sometimes draw from other texts, mostly limiting myself to Hegel’s
mature writings after the (1807) Phenomenology of Spirit. I
will very occasionally bring in evidence from the Phenomenology, but
only to help with the interpretation of arguments clearly present in later
writings.
2
Kant himself often connects parts and matter (KU 5:373) and later refers to
the ‘mechanism of matter’ (KU 5:410-1). And ‘their forces and their capacity
to combine by themselves’ might include, for example, gravity acting between
parts of a whole. Kant’s notion of mechanism does not exclude this; it
excludes explanatory reference to a unifying organization or pattern among
those parts. I am indebted to discussions of Kant’s sense of ‘mechanism’ in
McLaughlin (1990, 152f. ), Allison (1991), and especially Ginsborg (2001).
3
Or, this gives us no reason to doubt we can explain the movements of sea and
soil ‘without our regarding the sea as having acted on purpose’ (KU 5:368).
As Kant says, ‘even if all of this natural usefulness did not exist, we
would find nothing lacking in the adequacy of natural causes for this state
of things’ (KU 5:369).
4
More specifically, if I regard something as ‘a product of the mere mechanism
of matter’ then ‘I cannot derive the very same matter as a causality acting
according to ends. Conversely, if I assume that the same product is a
Naturzweck, I cannot count on a mechanical mode of generation ... For
one kind of explanation excludes the other’ (KU 5:412). Later, specifically
in terms of design: ‘Now if one asks why a thing exists, the answer is
either that its existence and its generation have no relation at all to a
cause acting according to intentions, and in that case one always
understands its origin to be in the mechanism of nature; or there is some
intentional ground of its existence’ (KU 5:425-6). I’ve defended in Kreines
(unpublished manuscript) a reading on which Kant has good reason to worry
about the problem presented by this conflict, does not simply dissolve or
dismiss the problem in later sections of the KU, and continues throughout to
deny the possibility of mechanistic and teleological
Erklärung of ‘one and the same thing in
nature’ (KU 5:411-2).
5
For example, the concept of natural purposiveness itself can be only ‘a
regulative concept for the reflecting power of judgment’ (KU 5:375).
Regarding the unsuitability of this for explanation, see: ‘teleological
judging is rightly drawn into our research into nature, at least
problematically, but only in order to bring it under principles of
observation and research in analogy with causality according to ends,
without presuming thereby to explain it (ohne sich anzumaßen sie
darnach zu erklären). It thus belongs to the reflecting, not to the
determining power of judgment’ (KU 5:360; Kant’s emphasis). ‘Positing ends
of nature in its products ... belongs only to the description of nature
(Naturbeschreibung)’ but ‘provides no information at all about the
origination and the inner possibility of these forms, although it is that
with which theoretical natural science is properly concerned’ (KU 5:417).
And: ‘the principle of ends in the products of nature ... does not make the
way in which these products have originated more comprehensible’ but is a
‘heuristic principle’ (KU 5:411).
6
I will not, then, explain Hegel’s argument in the Logic in terms of
his early Glauben und Wissen (1802) criticisms of Kant’s limited
employment of the notions of ‘intellectual intuition’ (intellektuelle
Anschauung) and ‘intuitive intellect’ (intuitive Verstand). I
think it is a mistake to assume that Hegel’s mature philosophy is best
understood in these terms, given that Hegel’s stress on these particular
Kantian terms declines and changes very early in his career. From the
Phenomenology on, for example, Hegel clearly criticizes the
idea (common to Fichte and Schelling in particular) of rehabilitating any
notion of ‘intellectual intuition’ (PG 23, §17; WL 5:65/67; 1:78-9/77-8).
Whether this is more a radical change of view, or more a radically new way
of explaining fundamentally continuous views—this depends on how we
interpret Hegel’s early writings, and I do not wish to take a stand on that
issue here. Instead, my aim is motivate a rethinking of Hegel’s mature
philosophical project by focusing specifically on the terms Hegel himself
uses in his mature writings to explain his criticism of mechanism.
Concerning Hegel’s changing stance on the ‘intuitive intellect’ in
particular, see Westphal (2000).
7
Bole and Stevens (1985) cite §85 in favor of a similar reading of the
general procedure of the Logic: ‘as each category arises within the
account of explanation offered by the Logic, it carries with it,
relative to that account, an implicit claim to be the thoroughgoing
explanation, or ultimate category, of explanation’ (119).
8
All objects would ‘remain external [äußerlich] to one another in
every combination. This is what constitutes the character of mechanism,
namely, that whatever relation obtains between the things combined, this
relation is one foreign to them that does not concern their nature’ (WL
6:409/711). Similarly, all relations would be ‘indifferent to what is so
related’ (WL 6:412/713). Compare similar uses of the term
‘external’ in Kant: ‘...wenn aber die Ursache bloß in der Materie, als einem
Aggregat vieler Substanzen außer einander, gesucht wird...’ (KU
5:421). And compare the first Critique on matter and ‘outer
relations’ (B333/A277). For a discussion of the way in which problems
similar to those which Hegel develops arise in Kant, see Kolb (1988).
9See
§205Z and also, in the Philosophy of Nature, Hegel’s joking about the
idea that ‘God’s wisdom is admired in that He has provided cork-trees for
bottle-stoppers, or herbs for curing disordered stomachs, and cinnabar for
cosmetics’ (§245Z). The joke about corks is borrowed from the Xenia,
written by Schiller and Goethe. Hegel blames this type of thought on
‘external purposiveness’ (§205Z).
10
For example, compare: ‘Hegel believes that mechanical and chemical
explanations are condemned always to remain incomplete, for they cannot be
applied to the totality of things to which they apply’ (deVries 1991,
66). Hegel does say that the mechanical object has ‘the determinateness of
its totality outside it in other objects,’ and that ‘these in turn have
theirs outside them, and so on to infinity’ (WL 6:412/713). But his point is
that while mechanistic accounts can keep expanding in breadth and narrowing
in focus, this produces only a great variety of new ways to describe what is
going on; it can generate neither reason to stop at any particular point,
nor reason to think progress is being made, nor indication of the direction
in which progress lies. Our procedure might as well stop at any arbitrary
point, or even before beginning; ‘it can halt and be satisfied at any point
at will’ (WL 6:412/713). Aside from the fact that Hegel’s argument does not
appeal to any supposed need for perfectly complete explanation in the
‘Mechanism’ section of the Logic, he also cuts the rug out from such
complaints by elsewhere denying that an account must be perfectly complete
to be explanatory. On the contrary, Hegel insists that ‘the dignity of
science must not be held to consist in the comprehension and explanation of
all the multiplicity of forms in nature... There is plenty that cannot be
comprehended yet...’ (§268Z). And this is fortunate, because such a
complaint about incompleteness would itself be, at best, incomplete. For
explaining could well be said to be to take a small but helpful step toward
an ideally complete explanation—even if we can never reach that ideal.
Compare for example Railton on the ‘ideal explanatory text’ (1981, 247).
11
It is interesting to note that this concern with explanation we’ve found
behind Hegel’s complaint about merely ‘external’ notions is a
straightforward extension of Kant’s use of ‘external’ (äußerlich) in
the KU. Kant complains that relations of benefit ground only ‘external’ or
‘contingent’ teleological characterizations of objects, in the sense that
there is no reason to think such characterizations really explain.
Hegel’s point is that the total mechanism hypothesis would render all
characterizations ‘external’ in just this sense—it would leave us
without any reason to regard any of them as explanatory.
12
Explanation, then, would involve describing in general terms that collect
together the ‘identical determinateness of different substances’ (WL
6:415/715). Compare also the similar way of putting things in the
Phenomenology: ‘The single occurrence of lightning, e.g., is
apprehended as a universal, and this universal is enunciated as the
law of electricity; the explanation then condenses the law
into force as the essence of the law.’ (PG 3:124/94)
13
Kant sometimes draws a comparable contrast between Regel and
Gesetz; see e.g. A113, A272/B328 and P 59/Ak. 4:312. Concerning this
line of argument, compare Quine’s effective elaboration: ‘What does it mean
to say that the kicking over of a lamp in Mrs. Leary’s barn caused the
Chicago fire? It cannot mean merely that the event at Mrs. Leary’s belongs
to a set, and the Chicago fire belongs to a set, such that there is
invariable succession between the two sets …. This paraphrase is trivially
true and too weak... We can rig the sets arbitrarily …. Because of this way
of trivialization, a singular causal statement says no more than that the
one event was followed by the other. That is, it says no more if we use the
definition just now contemplated; which, therefore, we must not’ (1969,
132).
14
Or, the supposed laws—under which we might unify causes of that sort and
effects of this sort—would themselves remain merely ‘external’ or
non-explanatory: ‘the objects are indifferent to this unity and maintain
themselves in the face of it’ (WL 6:415/715).
15
Also, even truly explanatory generalizations can also fail to explain events
which they would have predicted perfectly well. For example, the fact that
Pat regularly took birth control pills, conjoined with the relevant
statistical regularities concerning the effectiveness of the pills, gives us
good grounds to say that it is very unlikely Pat will become pregnant. But
we will not be inclined to say that any of this explains Pat’s
failure to become pregnant if Pat is male. The example is drawn from Salmon;
see his presentation of the relevance problem in (1984, 30ff). Also van
Fraassen (1980, 105) and Kitcher (1986)
16
Of course, Hegel cannot anticipate the entire series of 20th Century
attempts to distinguish explanation in terms of different formal models—for
example, Hempel’s claim that the explanation of a phenomenon must offer
factual information and general laws which together take the form of an
argument that the phenomenon occurs (1965,
367-8). But
Hegel’s general worry nonetheless applies, and he offers perfectly good
reasons to suspect that such proposals will not turn out to be any more
convincing than they have, in fact, turned out to be. This is, of course, no
reason to doubt the use of such formal models in classifying or considering
different sorts of explanations; the point is that explanation itself cannot
be distinguished by some such general model. In response to these sorts of
problems, contemporary philosophers tend either to advocate a stronger
realism than the positivist accounts would allow (e.g. Salmon 1984) or to
retreat from the objective notion of explanation toward a pragmatic or
interest-relative account (e.g. van Fraassen 1980, especially ch. 5).
17
For contemporary discussion of the connection between proposals of this sort
and the goal of theoretical inquiry, see e.g. Earman 1978, 180;
Kitcher 1986, 213; Loewer 1996, 112; Ward 2001.
18
The general debates concerning Hegel’s answer to this second sort of
question tend to focus less on the Logic and more on the
Philosophy of Nature. One popular view is that Hegel is there trying
to organize and systematize the empirical results of the sciences of his
day, presumably including mechanism. See e.g. Petry’s argument in his
‘Introduction’ to his edition of the Philosophy of Subjective Spirit
(1978). A traditional alternative is that Hegel advocates on a
priori grounds the sort of scientific claims which properly require
empirical grounds, and in particular denies on such illegitimate a priori
grounds that mechanism can truly or fundamentally explain. See e.g. van
Lunteren (1986) for a recent defense of this view with respect to Hegel on
Newton in particular. Both approaches seem to me to miss Hegel’s central
concern, at least in the Logic. There Hegel focuses on the
philosophical issues concerning the notion of explanation itself. Hegel’s
complaints about Newton there, for example, are neither a priori
arguments that Newton’s laws cannot explain, nor claims that Newton’s
results conflict with or are superseded by other contemporary scientific
discoveries. Hegel’s central point is that it is not possible to give, in
terms drawn from Newton’s theory, an account of why that theory should have
explanatory relevance—and that Newton does not have a satisfactory response
to this difficulty.
19
‘The ground of the movement of the planets round the sun is said to be the
attractive force of the earth and the sun on one another’; but this cannot
be explanatory if it really ‘expresses nothing other than what is contained
in the phenomenon’ (WL 6:98/458). This point is well explained in Inwood
(1983, 60-3) and Forster (1998, 66). Compare also a contemporary worry about
broadly Humean approaches to natural laws, for example in Dretske: ‘you
cannot make a generalization, not even a purely universal
generalization, explain its instances. The fact that every F
is G fails to explain why any F is G, and it fails
to explain it, not because its explanatory effects are too feeble to have
attracted our attention, but because the explanatory attempt is never even
made’ (1977, 262).
20
In the Logic Hegel worries that ‘many who come to these sciences with
an honest belief may well imagine’ that corresponding to the primary
scientific concepts are actual entities—e.g. forces—which have an ‘immediate
existence ... actually present in perception’ (WL 6:101/460). This
relates to another complaint Hegel has about Newton. Hegel takes Newton’s
claim that he has shown how gravity explains the observed phenomena, though
without explaining gravity itself (WL 6:102/ 461) to suggest that gravity
may be just another physical phenomenon to be explained like any other. And
Hegel takes this as a convenient way of suggesting, without having to argue,
that the distinction between explanation and description could be grounded
or accounted for without going beyond essentially mechanical accounts of
different objects bumping up against one another in space.
21
My reading in this section is much influenced by Inwood (1983) and
especially Forster (1998), but I disagree with both over this specific
point. Compare Inwood: “If they [purported real grounds such as God or
electricity –JK] have explanatory force, then there is a logical gap between
them and the phenomena which cannot ultimately be closed” (1983, 63). Inwood
sees the hole in this argument clearly: “the best response is to concede
that we cannot explain everything, that Hegel’s ideal of what an explanation
should be is not one that can be met” (1983, 63-4). That is precisely why it
is crucial that Hegel does not—contra Inwood—argue in this manner at all.
Forster similarly, in his account of the “empty word” passage (PG 3:122/93),
says: ‘since, on the realist model, a causal connection or force is supposed
to be something independent of the sensible occurrences which it
explains, the further question can always be asked why it … produces
sensible occurrences of the relevant kind, and this question remains
unanswered’ (1998, 65-6). I take it that some why-question would
always remain unanswered unless there were some way to account for
the totality of everything that is—and it would be question-begging to
merely assume the possibility of such a total explanation, and to criticize
mechanism in light of such an assumption.
22
Compare to Hegel’s charge that ‘necessity’ becomes an empty word to Lewis’
well-known response to Armstrong’s account of natural laws in terms of a
special relation ‘N’ between two ‘universals’: ‘Whatever N may be, I cannot
see how it could be absolutely impossible to have N(F,G) and Fa without Ga
…. The mystery is somewhat hidden by Armstrong’s terminology. He uses
“necessitates” as a name for the lawmaking universal N; and who would be
surprised to hear that if F “necessitates” G and a has F, then a must have
G? But I say that N deserves the name of “necessitation” only if, somehow,
it really can enter into the requisite necessary connections. It can’t enter
into them by being a name, any more than one can have mighty biceps just by
being called “Armstrong”’ (1999, 40).
23
That is, the problem in the Logic is not that ‘real ground’ proposals
would generate skepticism about explanatory knowledge; the problem is that
such proposals cannot account for the distinction between description and
explanation itself. The epistemological worries may play a role elsewhere
Hegel, however. See especially Forster (1998, 65-7) on the
Phenomenology.
24
Again, I’m indebted to Forster’s account of Hegel’s argument in the
Phenomenology as a realism/anti-realism dilemma concerning
explanation (1998, 67), despite the differences noted above.
25
See discussion and examples of the former type of reading in section 7 and
the notes below. Horstmann (1984 and 1990)—though not specifically focused
on the “Mechanism” section—sometimes gives a version of the second type of
reading, according to which Hegel argues as follows: Hegel’s anti-dualism
commits him to oppose Kant’s treatment of teleology and mechanism as two
fundamentally different forms of explanation with two different statuses;
but Hegel agrees with Kant that mechanism cannot for everything, because it
cannot account for organisms; so Hegel concludes that anti-dualism
requires the idea that everything can be considered as an organism, so that
mechanisms are just a special case of organisms (1984, 74-79; 1990, 50-54).
(Horstmann does also say, however, that there are other reasons why Hegel
finds attractive the idea of a superiority of teleology to mechanism.)
Pinkard suggests Hegel aims for a general criticism of mechanism itself, but
would have done better to limit himself to a defense of a distinct form of
teleological explanation in the specific case of purposive action: Hegel
‘has shown at best that a complete teleological explanation is logically
different from a mechanistic one, not that we fail to move on to
teleological explanations only on pain of self-contradiction or incoherence’
(1988, 91).
26
I thank Michael Della Rocca for a forceful formulation of this
counter-argument, and for pushing me to articulate Hegel’s answer. Also, a
contemporary approach along these lines is suggested by Lewis: ‘A Nominalist
could take it as a primitive fact that some classes of things are perfectly
natural properties; others are less-then-perfectly natural to various
degrees; and most are not at all natural’ (1999, 14).
27
I’m borrowing this manner of speaking from Strawson, e.g. ‘...these
necessary distinctions of temporal relation must be drawn within
experience...’ (1966, 27). Concerning this argument in Kant: ‘Only in this
way does there arise from this relation a judgment, i.e. a relation
that is objectively valid, and that is sufficiently distinguished
from the relation of these same representations in which there would be only
subjective validity, e.g., in accordance with laws of association’ (B142).
28
Ak 4:320/P 66. There is much dispute about the nature of the specific
problem Kant is worried about in the letter to Herz and its role in the
development of the critical philosophy; see Carl (1989), Beck (1989), and
Watkins (2001). I mean to remain neutral on this topic. I mean only to
insist that here, as in the Prolegomena citation, Kant is concerned
with some problem about the ‘agreement’ between subject and object, and that
he rules out ‘deus ex machina’ solutions to such problems.
29
In terms drawn from the PG, it would mean that ‘the true exists only in
what, or better as what, is sometimes called intuition, sometimes
immediate knowledge of the absolute, religion, or being’ (PG 15/4).
30
See Encyclopedia 8:23/11; 8:13/3; §5Z; §7A; §11A ; §24Z3; WL 5:65/67;
1:78-9/77-8. PG 4/15; 23/10.
31
Hegel often connects the appeal to immediate knowledge with the abandonment
of the project of philosophy. For example, Jacobi’s insistence that ‘we can
know only the finite and conditioned’ leads to ‘unmingled joy among men,
because the sloth of reason (thank God!) considered itself liberated from
every call to reflect.’ In particular, Jacobi’s insistence that any attempt
to comprehend the truth simply degrades the infinite into something
conditioned leads to Hegel’s lament: ‘Truth is in a bad way, when all
metaphysic is done away with, and the only philosophy acknowledged is no
philosophy at all!’ (VGP 20:384/3:476-7; see also
20:323). In Hegel’s discussion of Schelling he
says that, if we are supposed have a basic grasp of what we seek in
explanatory thinking by some means outside of thought, some form of
immediate knowing such as faith—if the ‘absolute cannot be cognized’ in this
sense—then philosophy will be ‘superfluous’ (VGP 20:248). In the PG Hegel’s
complaint looks like this: ‘If, namely, the true exists only in what, or
better as what, is sometimes called intuition, sometimes immediate
knowledge of the absolute, religion, or being ... then what is required in
the exposition of philosophy is, from this viewpoint, rather the opposite of
the form of the notion. For the absolute is not supposed to be comprehended,
it is to be felt and intuited; not the notion of the absolute but the
feeling and intuition of it, must govern what is said, and must be expressed
by it’ (PG 15/4).
32
Fichte (1845-6, I:463/1982, 38). See Pippin’s account of Fichte’s concern
with the problem of the explanation of such activity (2000, 156).
33
On the illegitimacy of attacking total mechanism by this means, see
especially Hegel’s complaint that one cannot refute Spinoza by merely
assuming the ‘freedom and self-subsistence of the self-conscious subject’
(WL 6:250/581). See also Hegel’s claim in the VGP that Fichte’s beginning
is, like previous metaphysics and Descartes in particular, another way of
appealing to something ‘immediate, not derived’ and so beyond any doubts;
Hegel proceeds to complain that this divides subject from object: ‘With this
reflection a false point of view was at once introduced, namely that
contained in the old conception of knowledge, of commencing with principles
in this form and proceeding from them; so that the reality which is derived
from such a principle is brought into opposition with it’ (VGP 20:392/485-6)
More specifically, this beginning will undermine our ability to address
these three questions about the relation between subject and object: (i) Why
should the results derived from such a principle be true of objects, rather
than just the way a self-conscious subject must think? (ii) How does the
subject originally grasp that there is an independent object to be known?
Hegel’s §60Z claims Fichte makes this inexplicable, and Fichte seems to cede
that something like this must be ‘incomprehensible’
(unbegreiflich) at (1945-6, I:177/1982,
164); see also Pippin’s discussion (1989, 57). (iii) How can the thoughts of
a spontaneous subject have any explanatory relevance to its actions in the
objective world? (This problem is the topic of the ‘Teleology’ section of
the Logic at WL 6:436-461/734-40; §204-12). I thank Steven Crowell
for pushing me to clarify the relationship between Hegel’s argument and the
‘easier route’ sketched in this paragraph.
34
Some examples: Not mechanism but rather ‘teleology is thus the category in
which we can account for the kind of totality Hegel envisages’ (Taylor 1975,
322). ‘We should bear in mind when considering any given thought the
possibility of applying it to God or to the universe as a whole. The
universe, as we have seen, cannot be adequately understood only as a
collection of causally interacting substances…’ (Inwood 1983, 346; see also
59-64). ‘Hegel believes that mechanical and chemical explanations are
condemned always to remain incomplete, for they cannot be applied to the
totality of things to which they apply...’ (deVries 1991, 66). Finally,
Horstmann’s (1991) account: Hegel conceives all of reality as based on a
primary structure which is itself an organic (or teleological) process (p.
180). The grounds of this preference for teleology are: (i) the need for a
‘unified and complete Weltbild’ which (ii) accounts for the
‘undifferentiated unity of thinking and being’ (p. 178).
35
Some examples of Hegel’s worries about earlier forms of monism: Spinoza’s
monism drags ‘what is finite into that same negative movement of the
understanding which makes everything vanish in the abstract unity of
substance’ (WL 5:121/214). Hegel also connects this point with the problem
of immediate knowledge: ‘Substance, as it is apprehended immediately by
Spinoza without preceding dialectical mediation—being the universal might of
negation—is only the dark, shapeless abyss, so to speak, in which all
determinate content is swallowed up as radically null and void, and which
produces nothing out of itself that has a positive subsistence of its own’
(§151Z). Famously, Hegel complains that beginning with an insistence that,
‘in the Absolute’ ‘all is one’ is to commit to the ‘undoing of all distinct,
determinate entities (or rather the hurling of them all into the abyss of
vacuity without further development or any justification),’ or to ‘the night
in which, as the saying goes, all cows are black’ (PG 3:22/9). Finally,
Plotinus and those modern philosophers attempting to revive the tradition of
neo-Platonism would like to explain all particulars in terms of ‘severance,
emanation, effluence’ out of pure being; ‘but in fact nothing is expressed’
by these words (VGP 19:463/429)—just as the total mechanism hypothesis makes
‘explanation’ into an empty word.
36
This is not a straw-man; it in fact is common to read Hegel has
making such fundamental assumptions. Two recent examples are Horstmann and
Siep. Horstmann says that Hegel is convinced of the necessity of assuming a
fundamental ‘zugrundeliegenden Primärstruktur’
behind everything that is. In this respect he fits ‘seamlessly’ into the
post-Kantian tradition of Fichte and Schelling—all have a ‘monistic
orientation’ which is defined by this assumption. Finally,
‘diese Überzeugung ist für Hegel daher auch nichts, was
einer elaborierten philosophischen Rechtfertigung bedarf.’ It must be
the foundation for philosophy because it is simply the only way to avoid all
previous failures to conceive a unified and complete Weltbild (1991,
177-8). (The question is, why assume the need for such a
Weltbild?) Siep (2000) claims that Hegel’s Phenomenology
project in particular is dependent on decisive but questionable
presuppositions drawn from pre-Kantian metaphysics, such as the idea that
nature is a complete and totally interconnected whole (p. 19) and the
possibility of a complete synthesis of religious and scientific knowledge
(p. 18). This involves a sort of
‘Einheitsspekulation’ which assumes just those
claims rendered questionable by Kant’s critical philosophy (p. 21).
37
E.g. Guyer: ‘Hegel does not examine Kant’s own reasons for his subjectivism,
and thus neither shows why Kant’s subjectivist scruples are invalid nor how
his own view can transcend them’ (1993, 171-2). Instead, Hegel ‘criticized
Kant’s conclusions from the point of view of his own suppositions about the
bond between knowledge and reality’ (1993, 204). With respect specifically
to the issues concerning mechanism and teleology, Düsing argues as follows:
Hegel’s objections to Kant’s treatment in the KU do not apply to Kant,
because Hegel ignores Kant’s arguments for the regulative status of the
maxims of mechanism and teleology, which would render teleology and
mechanism compatible. Hegel is guided instead by his own incompatible
assumptions: ‘Hegel hat jedoch bei seiner Kritik eine
ganz andere, nämlich seine eigne spekulativ-dialektische Konzeption, vor
Augen. Danach gilt es, die Dinge der Welt selbst, d.h. die Dinge an sich,
nicht nur die raum-zeitlichen Erscheinungen, zu Erkennen, und zwar auch in
einander widersprechenden Bestimmungen’ (1990, 152).
38
See especially Hartmann’s formulation: Hegel advocates a ‘non-metaphysical
philosophy devoid of existence claims and innocent of a reductionism opting
for certain existences to the determinant of others’ (Hartmann 1976b, 110).
This is to give an essentially Kantian reading even of Hegel’s claim for the
‘unity of the notion and objectivity’ (§213). As
Hartmann puts it, ‘Begriffe, deren “Fassung” als Einheit von Sein und
Begriff gelingt, wären Kategorien’ (Hartmann 1976a, 2).
Another non-metaphysical interpretation, with a very different
reading of the way in which Hegel’s objectivity claim is essentially
Kantian, see Pippin (1989, especially p. 6), and Siep’s (1991) response that
this approach captures many insights but fails to grasp the whole of Hegel’s
truly metaphysical project.
39
I am not of course the first to propose an alternative to these readings,
but I find that most proposed alternatives turn out to be versions of the
metaphysical reading, along with all its disadvantages. For example, Beiser
complains about a ‘false dilemma’ here (1995, 3). His alternative looks like
this: Hegel ‘accepted the concept of the infinite in the broad Spinozian
sense as that of which nothing greater can be conceived,’ and then reasoned
that ‘the absolute cannot be some supersensible reality behind appearances’
but must be ‘the whole of all that exists,’ and that philosophy ‘has to be
systematic: only a system of all essential concepts can be adequate to its
object, the universe as a whole’ (1995, 4). But it follows that philosophy
must be such as to be adequate to this object only if we assume that
Spinoza’s concept of the infinite is necessarily instantiated, and this is a
paradigmatic example of the pre-critical metaphysical claims that Kant
attacks (most explicitly in his critique of the ontological argument). To
see Hegel as simply assuming something like this
is—paradigmatically—to advocate a metaphysical reading of Hegel which
renders response to Kant question-begging. Beiser offers Hegel’s claim from
the VGP that ‘Spinoza’s substance is the starting point of philosophy’ (p.
13) as interpretive evidence for his reading. But Hegel clearly does not
advocate this as an assumption. Hegel criticizes Spinoza and
the traditional versions of the ontological argument on precisely this
score: ‘The defect in Anselm’s argumentation, however, which is also shared
by Descartes and Spinoza, as well as by the principle of immediate knowing,
is that this unity, which is proclaimed as most perfect (or
subjective as the true knowing) is presupposed’ (§193A; also VGP
19:557).
40
Concerning this Hegel’s contrast between critical philosophy and appeals to
immediacy, he also also says that Jacobi’s philosophy, in which ‘immediacy
is grasped as absolute,’ ‘zeigt den Mangel aller Kritik, aller Logik’ (VGP
20:327/3:421).
41
‘The proper principle of reason in general (in its logical use) is to find
the unconditioned for conditioned cognitions’ (A307/B364).
42
‘Reality in space, i.e. matter, is likewise something conditioned,
whose inner conditions are its parts’ (A413/B440).
43
‘Either reason, in demanding the unconditioned, must remain in conflict with
itself, or else this unconditioned must be posited outside the series in the
intelligible realm’ (A564/B592). Hegel follows this reasoning closely in the
VGP, noting Kant’s insistence that ‘no psychologically sensuous intuition or
perception corresponds with the infinite,’ and that the categories (thought
objectively valid) must remain ‘subjective’ specifically because ‘the
infinite, so far as it is defined by means of categories, loses itself in
contradictions’ (VGP 20:353/3:444-5).
44
In other words: Hegel interprets the critical insight to be that there can
be no authority beyond thought or pure reason, because any appeal to
immediate knowledge allows merely subjective criteria for knowledge, which
makes philosophy superfluous; Kant’s limitation of our knowledge (Hegel
argues) requires him to make such an appeal; so the critical insight cuts
against the limitation of our knowledge. Hegel tends to make this case by
asserting a fundamental similarity between Kant and Jacobi. For example:
‘With Kant ... the result is: “We know only phenomena;” with Jacobi, on the
other hand, it is: “We know only the finite and conditioned.” Over these two
results there has been unmingled joy among men, because the sloth of Reason
(thank God!) considered itself liberated from every call to reflect ... The
further result attending this is the autocracy of the subjective reason,
which, seeing that it is abstract and without knowledge, has only subjective
certainty and not objective truth’ (VGP 20:384/3:476-7). Hegel actually
connects Kant and Jacobi throughout his discussion of both in the VGP, even
before turning his attention to each, see 20:315/3:410; also
VGP 20:383/3:475. It is fascinating in this
context that Kant appears to engage with the sort of worries Hegel would
later raise, specifically in a letter to Jacobi (Ak 11:76/C 319); Jacobi
himself highlights this passage in his response (Ak 11:103/C 323).
Concerning Hegel’s connection between Kant and Jacobi, he does also note
differences in their accounts of ‘Glaube’ (VGP 20:323) and Jacobi’s
critique of Kant (WL 5:99/95). And Hegel connects the two in praise as well:
e.g. he says that Kant and Jacobi succeed in rendering obsolete the style
and method of previous metaphysics, exemplified in particular by Spinoza and
Wolff; Kant does so by means of the antinomies (WL 6:539/816).
45
This point is central to Hegel’s revision of Kant’s notion of ‘dialectic.’
See e.g. §11A: ‘When thinking despairs of being able to bring about, from
its own resources (aus sich), the resolution of the contradiction in
which it has put itself’ it must not ‘degenerate into misology ...
which is what happens when a so-called immediate knowing is asserted
to be the exclusive form of the consciousness of truth.’
46
Hegel emphasizes in the PG that his promise that the project can succeed in
winning cognition of the absolute must be provisional. For the purposes of
explanation of the project, he makes the promise, ‘even though it must for
the present be no more than a bare assertion, like the view it contradicts’.
That competing view is that ‘the true exists only in what, or better
as what, is sometimes called intuition, sometimes immediate knowledge
of the absolute’ (PG 15/4).
47
From the critique of Jacobi: ‘inspiration, revelation of the heart, a
content implanted in man by nature, and in particular, sane human
understanding (or “common sense”) as well. All of these forms similarly make
immediacy—i.e., the way that a content is found within consciousness, and is
a fact in it—into their principle’ (§63A). On the connection between appeals
to common sense and immediacy see also VGP 20:291 and PG 63/41.
48
Hegel summarizes this extended argument that objective or intrinsic
‘notions’ are required for persisting individual objects of thought as
follows: ‘The onward movement of the notion [Begriff] is no longer
transition [Übergehen] into, or a reflection on something else, but
development [Entwicklung]. For in the notion [Begriff], the
elements distinguished are without more ado at the same time declared to be
identical with one another and with the whole...’ (§161). My sketch of this
line of thought draws from Pinkard (1988, 55-6) and Pippin (1989, 192-3 and
206).
49
Stern (1990) is an excellent and comprehensive argument for a version of the
type of reading sketched here. For some evidence in favor of the distinction
between notions and ordinary predicates, see e.g. the ‘Preface’ to the
second edition of the WL: ‘…each human individual [menschliche
Individuum], though infinitely unique, is so primarily because he is
human … if this is true, then it would be impossible to say what such
an individual could still be if this foundation were removed’ (WL 5:25/36;
also §24Z). And see Wolff’s reading on organic objects
and determinate individuality: ‘anorganischen Objekten … diejenige
Individualität fehlt, die erforderlich ist, um sie also bestimmte reale
Einzeldinge identifizieren zu können’ (Wolff 1991, 203).
50
In this respect I follow a path mapped out by Horstmann, though to a
somewhat different destination. The path looks like this: Hegel appears to
connect the conditions of true objecthood to organicism. But he does not
mean to require that all objects must be organisms. He means that the
conditions of objecthood can be specified only with reference to the
structure characteristic of ‘subjectivity,’ or conscious living beings in
particular (1984, 85; 1990, 62).
51
That is to say that Hegel would like to argue: (i) no natural kind has a
perfectly internal or intrinsic notion, (ii) but Geist does, because
it is self-forming or ‘free.’ In Hegel’s terms: ‘In nature, not only is the
play of forms a prey to the boundless and unchecked contingency, but each
shape is without the Notion of itself. The highest level to which Nature
attains is life; but this, as only a natural mode of the idea, is at the
mercy of the unreason of externality, and the living creature is throughout
its whole life entangled with other alien existences, whereas in every
expression of Geist there is contained the moment of free, universal
self-relation’ (§248A). See also the transition in the WL from ‘Life’ to
‘Cognition,’ where Hegel contrasts merely biological life with
‘freie Gattung für sich selbst in die
Existenz’ (§222). On the contrast between the development of
self-conscious Geist and the changes in biological species, see the
WL on freedom and fate (WL 6:421/720-1), and also EL §234Z, the
Philosophy of Nature §370A and §392A, PG 224-5/178-9, and the
Philosophy of Geist §381Z.
52
This account specifically of explanation and laws is clearest at the
beginning of the Philosophy of Nature. There Hegel formulates the
issue of explanatory status as a problem about ‘the necessity’ of
nature’s formations (§250)—that is, the problem of why some ways of grouping
natural phenomena can capture necessary and so explanatory laws, and some
cannot. The problem with this is the potential conflict with the
‘indifferent contingency and indeterminable irregularity’ (§250) of
those natural forms. For we find no ‘fixed distinctions for classes and
orders from an empirical consideration of Nature,’ nor can we ‘deduce’ such
concepts (§250). Hegel’s proposal is that the necessity of nature’s forms is
‘generated by the notion’ insofar as these are subject to ‘rationally
determination’ in an ‘organic totality’ (§250). That is, the explanatory
status of certain laws and concepts is not given but forged in the
process of rational inquiry into the best overall organized (‘organic’)
theoretical system for understanding nature. Also on necessity in particular
see also §232.
53
My stress on this point is controversial, so it is worth considering some
additional evidence. This cited passage continues: ‘The highest level to
which Nature attains is life; but this, as only a natural mode of the idea,
is at the mercy of the unreason of externality, and the living creature is
throughout its whole life entangled with other alien existences’ (§248A).
Also on biology in particular: ‘Almost less even than the other spheres of
nature, can the animal world exhibit within itself an independent, rational
system of organization’ (§370). And life ‘in its differentiating process
does not actually posses any rational ordering and arrangement of parts, and
is not an immanently grounded system of shapes’ (PG 224-5/178-9).
54
Matter is the ‘universal basis of every existent form in nature’ and ‘offers
resistance to us, exists apart from our mind’ (§381Z). See also Pippin’s
(1997) similar use of this passage.
55
Hegel criticizes assumptions about unity which play a role in the
traditional ontological argument and also in Spinoza’s monism, connecting
such assumptions specifically with claims for immediate knowledge: ‘The
defect in Anselm’s argumentation, however, which is also shared by Descartes
and Spinoza, as well as by the principle of immediate knowing, is that this
unity, which is proclaimed as most perfect (or subjective as the true
knowing) is presupposed’ (§193A).
56
With the emphasis on the self-forming of Geist, Hegel insists that
philosophy ‘steps out of Spinozism (aus dem Spinozismus heraustritt)’
(§415A). See also VGP 3:459/449-550. With respect to Spinoza see also WL
5:98-9/94-5; 5:178-9/160-1.
57
For generous and helpful comments, suggestions and discussion of this work,
I would like to thank Troy Cross, Steven Crowell, Michael Della Rocca,
Michael Forster, Desmond Hogan, Shelly Kagan, David McNeill, Robert Pippin,
and Candace Vogler. I am also grateful to the participants in helpful
discussions of earlier drafts at a Yale faculty colloquium and also a group
meeting of the Society for German Idealism at the American Philosophical
Association, Pacific Division in 2003.