James Kreines
jkreines@cmc.edu
Draft. Please cite
from the final
version forthcoming in The
Oxford
Handbook of Hegel, ed. Dean Moyar
Hegel is difficult to interpret, and the
Science of Logic
especially difficult. The conclusion of the book centers on the
transition to the last section, “The Idea”, and the transition to
the last chapter in that section, “The Absolute Idea”. Of course,
Hegel’s own terminology is among the considerable difficulties. But
I think that it is possible to understand the arguments here, to
give an account in independently accessible philosophical terms, and
to uncover some strengths of lasting philosophical interest. I argue
that there are two keys:
First, the
Logic takes a kind of
metaphysics as fundamental within philosophy. This is not to deny
that Hegel addresses other topics, such as epistemology. But the
Logic ultimately argues
that other issues should be understood and addressed in metaphysical
terms. So the Logic does
not seek an epistemologically specified ultimate end, such as that
of indubitable and foundational
knowledge—making
secondary the question of what, if any, metaphysics would serve that
end. And the problems the
Logic takes as basic, in the end, do not descend from those Kant
seeks to resolve by means of the deductions of the Transcendental
Analytic of the first
Critique, concerning the relation between cognition or concepts
and objects. The Logic
will give priority rather to metaphysical problems drawn from Kant’s
Transcendental Dialectic, and this provides the unity and
philosophical force of the arguments that conclude the
Logic.
Second, those who see a metaphysics in Hegel
tend to see one that is specifically monistic, descended from
Spinoza’s or from neo-Platonism. But I argue that the metaphysics at
the end of the Logic is
very different. I take “metaphysical foundationalism” to be the view
that there is some sufficient reason or ground for everything, on
which everything depends while it depends on nothing. Metaphysical
monism is a specific version: the foundation is the One that
everything is “in”. But Hegel’s own conclusions, I will argue, are
no form of metaphysical foundationalism at all—neither a
scientistic, theological, nor monistic form. There is, to be sure,
something that is first in metaphysical priority: the absolute idea.
But, as Hegel often says, the end is what is first: what is most
mediated and even, in a sense, dependent (the end) is also first, or
of highest metaphysical priority. But this claim is difficult, and
requires much preparation.
1. Topic: Kant’s Dialectic and Hegel’s Metaphysics of Reason
In this section, I want to work from a
connection to Kant towards a way of explaining the topic addressed
by the end of the Logic
in independently accessible philosophical terms. I begin with Kant’s
account of the “faculty of reason” (Vernunft)
in the Transcendental Dialectic of the first
Critique. Kant here
argues that we have an ineliminable need for a goal to guide or
regulate the use of our theoretical faculties. The faculty of reason
is supposed to provide this, insofar as it directs us away from
incurious satisfaction with the surface of things, demanding that we
instead assume for the sake of inquiry that things have further
explanations, and to seek to find the
conditions or grounds in
terms of which they could be explained—and ultimately
the unconditioned, where
this is the notion of something to which one could appeal in
explaining completely, or
a complete explainer.[1] In
the Dialectic’s technical terms, “ideas” are specifically ideas of
the unconditioned (A334-7/B391-4). And Kant concludes, given the
ineliminable guiding role of reason, that metaphysical questions
about such ideas are inescapable for us (A421/B449). So there is an
of inescapability of questions on the domain of the
metaphysics of reason, as
I will call it; those who pretend indifference to them are
unknowingly assuming answers, if they continue to think at all (Ax).
But Kant also argues that we cannot answer
those questions. He does so by arguing that all of the obvious
approaches to the inescapable topic are unacceptable.
First, we could hold that
there must always be unconditioned grounds. This is one specific way
of pursuing the metaphysics of reason: the rationalist way, built
around the principle of sufficient reason (PSR).[2] Kant
seeks to explain a kind of inevitable rational appeal of
metaphysical rationalism, but in a manner demonstrating that
philosophy should never assert such a view or draw such conclusions.
For the Antinomy of Pure Reason argues that this view generates
contradictions; rationalism can escape direct self-contradiction
only in versions that both rest on principles like the PSR and yet
would equally be undercut by those same principles—only in a
“dogmatic stubbornness, setting its mind rigidly to certain
assertions without giving a fair hearing to the grounds for the
opposite” (A407/B434).
Second, there are negative responses. But to deny the existence
of any and all forms of the unconditioned would merely be the
opposite form of dogmatism (A471/B499). And other forms of
skepticism or indifferentism concerning the unconditioned are, Kant
says, impossible, and anyway an unacceptable “euthanasia
of pure reason” (A407/B433-4). So Kant concludes that a
third response is
necessary, one which is supposed to be radical and new. The full
story of this resolution of the antinomy problems is the package of
views that comprise transcendental idealism (A491/B519).
For our purposes the crucial part of this package is the conclusion
that we have strict epistemic limits—fixed by our sensibility and
its pure forms, space and time. For from this it will follow that
philosophy can legitimately conclude neither that there are any
unconditioned grounds, nor that there are none. Thus philosophy
cannot answer metaphysical questions, at least in this sense of
“metaphysics” that is supposed to be of most direct and inescapable
rational interest.
Kant’s aim here is not to give up on
theoretical philosophy; it is to transform it into a new kind of
project—as pursued, for example, in the Transcendental Analytic
consideration of the necessary conditions of the possibility of
cognition of objects. (We need not resolve, for our purposes,
whether the basic topic there is more narrowly
epistemological—concerned with knowledge, justification, etc.—or
more about issues we might now call “semantic”, concerning the very
possibility of aboutness, objective purport, intentionality, etc.
For the sake of having a term, I call all such issues about
relations between cognition and objects “broadly epistemological”.)
What is important is that there are senses in which the new project
is supposed to be a transformed version of “metaphysics”. For
example, it is not empirical; it offers, in the face of doubts, a
justification of the synthetic
a priori.
So the new project seeks to “transform the accepted procedure of
metaphysics” (Bxxii), and will take as basic such broadly
epistemological notions as a
priori. But note that the Dialectic does not merely
presume anything like
this priority of epistemology. It does not in particular argue
from claims about our
epistemic limits, because it could not then
support such claims.
It argues that a more direct engagement with metaphysics is
necessary, but then comes into conflict with itself, calling itself
into question.
Now Hegel will take on board much from Kant,
before then diverging: Yes, it is necessary to directly engage the
metaphysics of reason; skepticism or indifferentism about reason is
unacceptable; metaphysics generates necessary conflicts; and these
conflicts do end the prospects for pre-Kantian metaphysics.
But Hegel will argue that
the considerations of Kant’s Dialectic nonetheless support no
epistemic limitations, and no exit from direct consideration of the
metaphysics of reason—no transformation after which metaphysics
would be engaged from the perspective of broadly epistemological
issues. Considerations in Kant’s Dialectic are rather supposed to
support a new and different constructive metaphysics of reason.
And so we can give an explanation of the topic
at the end of the Logic,
in a manner that clarifies Hegel’s terminology in independently
accessible philosophical terms. The topic is metaphysics, in the
sense of general and direct questions about
why or
because of things, about
that in the world to which one would have to appeal in explaining
and ultimately explaining completely. It concerns what Hegel calls
“reason” (Vernünft) or
“the rational” (das
Vernünftige) “in the world”.[7] For
example, according to this
metaphysics of reason conception, the point of a
materialist metaphysics
would be this: reason is in the world only in a way in which
everything real is (the materialist claims) grounded in basic
matter, which is itself brute, lacking any further reason or
grounds. But Hegel’s own specific view will not be materialist.
Hegel seeks to argue that there is a more complete form of reason,
or something to which one could appeal in explaining completely.
Hegel , borrowing from Kant, calls this “the idea”. Kant would call
it “the unconditioned”, and while Hegel sometimes borrows this last
term, he also worries about it (EL §45). In part, Hegel worries that
this term makes it too easy for Kant to connect the topic with
specifically rationalist notions—such as substance as a substrate
with attributes “in” it. To bring the overall ambition together in a
main point, Hegel wants to argue that “the idea”, or completeness of
reasons, must be understood in terms of unconditionedness in the
different sense of a kind of active self-determination. Thus:
The idea is the
rational (Vernünftige);
- it is the unconditioned, because only that has conditions which
essentially refers to an objectivity that it does not determine
itself… (WL 6:463/671)
And Hegel will
argue that, once “the idea” is better understood in this way, there
will no longer be grounds for Kant’s claim that it is unknowable for
us, and no sense in which attention to reason suggests any in
principle limits to our knowledge at all.
Understanding the details requires travelling a
long road. What is crucial at the start is that we resist the
temptation to epistemologize the notion of “reason” and the
corresponding project. For Hegel’s aim is to show that the Dialectic
fails before it justifies
Kant’s transformation of metaphysics, or the shift onto broadly
epistemological ground, or ground of Kantian deductions, etc. So
“reason” here is precisely not
at base given content by notions like that of justification, as
for example where one might give someone a justification for one’s
claim, or ask for such justification, etc. And Hegel’s project is in
this respect unlike one that would begin with a sense of “reasons”
resting on a supposedly basic contrast between reasons and causes,
or the normative and the nomological, or similar. Hegel’s arguments
have implications concerning these topics—for what we would call
“normativity”, for example—but he addresses these in terms of an
underlying metaphysics, including issues about whether and how it
might be possible to account for and justify a distinction between
normative and non-normative forms of
reason in the world, and
a metaphysical priority for the former. Similarly, the ultimate aim
is not epistemologically specifiable—for example as
a priori results,
independent of the empirical; the ultimate end lies more directly
within metaphysics, even if the means must be in some senses an
a priori method.
And, finally, my point of stressing reason
in the world is not to
suggest any priority of either world or mind in addressing broadly
epistemological questions about the possibility of cognition of
objects; the point is that the basic issues lie elsewhere, with this
at base metaphysical rather than epistemic notion of reason.
To be sure, Hegel does agree with Kant that
pre-Kantian philosophy is unacceptably dogmatic. But
Hegel’s point is not what
we would ordinarily expect from such agreement. It is not that the
topic of Kant’s deductions is so fundamental that any philosophy
without them implicitly assumes an unacceptably immediate identity
of cognition and reality. It is not that pre-Kantian philosophy
fails because it is not yet properly set on basis of such
deductions. Rather, Hegel finds pre-Kantian philosophy dogmatic
because it does not face directly its own assumptions about the
metaphysics of reason in the world, and the ways that these generate
the conflicts uncovered by Kant’s Dialectic. This emphasis on the
Dialectic contradictions is what Hegel means in approaching
metaphysics under the heading “logic”: “the dialectic makes up the
very nature of thinking,” and “a cardinal aspect of logic” (EL
§11R). And so Hegel’s Logic
sees in Kant an “insight” crucial to an “elevation of reason to
the loftier spirit of modern philosophy”; but this is
not any insight about any
need for Kant’s Analytic deductions; it is “insight into the
necessary conflict” (WL 5:38–39/25–26)—the topic of the
Dialectic. In some senses the
Logic tests, at earlier points, projects more like Kant’s
positive project; but these are supposed to fail until and unless
they are finally reshaped or transformed by the way the end of the
Logic recognizes a
priority of metaphysics.
So the project concluding at the end of the
Logic will neither be a
version of Spinoza’s rationalism, nor of Kant’s positive project in
the Transcendental Analytic. It is more distinctively Hegel’s own:
it is to use the supposedly negative or destructive considerations
of Kant’s Dialectic critique of metaphysics for the purposes of
reconstruction—to rebuild metaphysics on the grounds of the
strongest criticism of it.
2. Defense and Application of the Concept Thesis: Mechanism and
Teleology
The final sections of the
Science of Logic are as
follows:
THE DOCTRINE OF THE CONCEPT
. . .
B. Objectivity:
(a) Mechanism
(b) Chemism
(c) Teleology
C. The Idea
(a) Life
(b) The Idea of Cognition
(c) The absolute Idea
Here Hegel is, in part, concluding his
defense of a basic thesis, which I would name and express in this
way:
The
concept thesis: the reasons which explain why things are as
they are and do what they do are always found in immanent “concepts”
(Begriffe), akin to
immanent universals or kinds (Gattungen).[9]
Hegel
will apply this thesis in such a manner as to distinguish different
logics of different forms of reason in the world, or different sorts
of immanent concepts or
Begriffe. First, take something which behaves lawfully, as with
the rotation of the planets discussed in “Mechanism”: why does it do
what it does? On account of immanent “concepts” in the sense of the
natures of such things which make them what they are, and more
specifically the powers that such things have in virtue of this
nature of their kind. For example, the planets rotate on account of
gravitation being the nature of matter, or because
“gravitation is the true and determinate concept of material
corporeality” (PN §269).
Second, take a living being, as discussed in “Life”: why does it do
what it does? On account of the “concept” in the sense of the
biological species or kind, and more specifically the distinctive
ways in which its species seeks the immanent end of
self-preservation. Third, take the sorts of beings who can more
specifically grasp concepts and so engage in
cognition: why do we do
what we do? On account of our immanent “concept,” the concept of
“spirit”, which turns out to be not just any concept but “the
concept”, and whose content turns out to be
freedom.
On this account, immanent concepts—at least in
the case of nature—are discovered by the natural sciences. But
defense of the concept thesis itself is a different matter. Here
Hegel gives, within metaphysics, a distinctly philosophical defense,
arguing that the thesis is inescapable for any possible philosophy:
the considerations which most seem to threaten it will in fact turn
out to support it. For Hegel, the most important such case comes
near the conclusion of the
Logic, in the
“Mechanism” chapter. But
the way to understand this is as concluding a line of argument begun
earlier, excluding different ways of avoiding the concept thesis:
First,
Hegel draws everywhere on the idea that explanation must be, at
least in part, subject to a kind of worldly constraint. Explaining
why things are as they are or do what they do requires more than
formulating a way of describing things that seems explanatory to
some audience. This perhaps clearest where Hegel notes kinds of
accounts—like those in astrology or phrenology—which
might seem compelling in context of some audiences, but cannot truly
explain in any context at all.
Second,
one of course try to understand the worldly constraint on
explanation without any appeal to reason in the world at all. One
might understand explanation rather in terms of what Hegel calls,
earlier in the Logic,
“formal ground”. On this kind of view, successful explanation
would not require anything in the world over and above what happens
or how things actually develop—or the facts which make true a
description with a certain
form, such as that of a universal generalization. But the
Logic argues that such
grounds would have to be “a mere formalism, the empty tautology of
repeating,” where nothing is “explained by this formalism” (WL
6:98/400). For noting that something regularly happens is not to
explain why it happens, but just to repeat that it happens in this
case as well as others. So there are grounds to conclude, with
Hegel, that the worldly constraint on explanation would have to be
understood in terms of something over and above the happenings or
developments to be explained—in terms of a
reason for them. Reason
in the world, then, is the metaphysical side of explanation.
For example, take accounts of our behavior in terms of bumps on
skulls. Someone might gerrymander their way to correlations between
certain bump-shapes and certain behavior. But no such correlations
would explain, regardless of audience, because they fail to identify
any real form of reason in the world; behavior is in fact
“indifferent” (Gleichgültig)
to gerrymandered bump-shapes on the skull, where “indifference”
means the lack of any form reason in the world.
Third,
one could grant an understanding of explanation in terms of reason
in the world, but seek to avoid the conclusion that the reasons for
things are specifically concepts. This is where Hegel sees a crucial
competitor in appeals to mechanism. The idea would be what I call
“pure” or “conceptless” mechanism: for any whole object, a supposed
nature or concept of this kind of whole will be of no explanatory
relevance to what it does; all the explanatory work would be done
insofar as every whole is mechanistic, or (in Kant’s terms) the
“product of the parts and of their forces and their capacity to
combine by themselves” (KU 5:408). But Hegel argues that pure
mechanism undercuts its own coherence. With pure mechanism each and
every object
…points for its determinateness outside and
beyond itself, constantly to objects for which it is however
likewise a matter of indifference that they do the determining… (WL
6:412/633)
So no way of redescribing, breaking things
down into wholes and parts, would be privileged over or better than
any other when it comes to explaining, and all would be equally
arbitrary or a matter of subjective preference. All would be equally
indifferent. Note that
Hegel’s argument does not assume that everything can be explained
completely, and then criticize mechanism with this assumed but
question-begging standard.
Pure mechanism sets the standard by which it fails, in arguing that
appeal to immanent concepts are superfluous
because the real explanation
is rather always mechanistic.
No one can coherently make that proposal, because by his own lights,
“…to explain
the determination of an object, and to this end to extend
the representation of it beyond it, is only an
empty word” (WL
6:412/633).
Fourth,
one might think that this mechanism argument leaves open the real
competitor to Hegel’s immanent concepts, namely, mechanistic
forces or
laws as a kind of “real
ground” external to what
they explain. But the Logic
has already shown that this is the other side a dilemma, along
with “formal ground” above. The point is that it is impossible to
make sense of the reasons for things—and so of explanation—at this
earlier stage of the Logic,
prior to the development of the metaphysics of immanent concepts
concluding the Logic. We
would in particular need immanent concepts
of such external forces
or laws themselves, if we are to account for the explanatory import
of these. So avoiding immanent concepts by positing forces or laws
as real or external grounds makes no progress, and would leave us
wanting to posit unknown further grounds for grounds, and so on
forever
(WL 6:102/402).
Thus
Hegel draws his metaphysical conclusion: there are reasons for
things, over and above what happens (contra “formal ground”), but
(contra “real ground”) they are rooted in immanent concepts. With
respect to mechanistic cases specifically, the result is what I call
“reasonable” mechanism: some things (not all) are explicable in
mechanistic terms, in terms of laws, in virtue of the immanent
concept of matter.
Hegel’s central example is the rotation of the solar system. First,
this has a reason in the world (“its reason”):
The movement of the solar system is governed
by unalterable laws; these laws are its reason. But neither the sun
nor the planets which revolve around it are conscious of them…
[T]here is reason in nature…
And the law that is
its reason is rooted in the immanent concept of matter, which is
gravitation. With respect to these rotating material bodies, then,
“law is indeed immanent in them and it does constitute their nature
and power,” as Hegel puts it at the end of “Mechanism” (WL
6:428/644).
With this sketch of the
defense in hand, we can
now turn to the application
of the concept thesis. The most important issues concern the
possibility of a teleological and so normative form of immanent
concept. Hegel raises the central problem here in the “Teleology”
chapter, near the conclusion of the
Logic. We tend to think
that it is enough, to introduce teleology into an otherwise lawful
or necessity-governed world, to introduce conscious representations
of purposes or ends as efficient causes. And since the rise of the
modern sciences, philosophers have tended to want to restrict
teleology to cases involving such representations. But Hegel argues
for the contrary view he traces to Aristotle:
With regard to the purpose, one should not
immediately or should not merely think of the form in which it is in
consciousness… in the
representation. (EL #204Anmerkung).
Hegel, drawing on a distinction from Kant,
calls this “external” teleology. And Hegel argues that,
if the world were
otherwise entirely necessity-governed, then the addition of external
teleology, or “the subjective purpose”, would be a matter of
“objective indifference” (Gleichgültigkeit)
with respect to what happens (WL 6:447/658)—such purposes would not
be the reason for anything at all. So
if there are any
teleological forms of reason in the world (including the purposive
behavior of intelligent agents), then there must be at least some
form of teleology independent of such causation by external
subjective representations of ends—there must be
also what Kant calls
“inner purposiveness”.
This is to raise a problem, because Kant’s own
point about this is largely skeptical. True, Kant argues that we
judge organisms in terms of inner purposiveness, or as “natural
purposes” (Naturzwecke),
and that such judgment plays an ineliminable guiding role; but it is
impossible (Kant argues) for us to know whether there is any such
thing as a Naturzweck or
any real inner purposiveness.
Crucial to Kant’s case is his insight that we
cannot analyze teleology in metaphysically deflationary terms—say,
as just one among many of our explanatory practices, or ways of
describing the structure of things or how they in fact develop. To
simplify Kant’s example, the arctic ecosystem developed in such a
way that seals benefit humans. Deflationary accounts constraining
only structure or development will be subject to examples like this,
where they can be forced to hold that this development of benefit
justifies finding a teleological kind of intelligibility, concluding
that the telos of seals
is to benefit humans. But the fact of benefit justifies no such
teleology (KU 5:369). This is clearest in considering the
normativity that comes with teleology (EE 20:240): clearly benefit
does not justify the conclusion that seals have the normative
function of benefiting humeans, so that those evading capture are
malfunctioning. Thus
for real teleology, something is required over and above a structure
with benefits, namely a specific kind of
reason for this
structure: beneficial parts must be present
because of their benefit
in relation to the whole.
The obvious way that this requirement could be met is by artifacts
that are the product of external design. For example, a gear in a
watch comes to be present because of its benefit in relation to the
way the whole serves the designer’s end of reliable indication of
the time (KU 5:374). This makes the watch a purpose or
Zweck. But for the
inner purposiveness of a
Naturzweck, there
is a second requirement: purpose must be not imposed from without,
but stem from the parts within the system.
The problem is that we cannot, Kant argues,
know these two requirements to be jointly met. With respect to
organisms specifically, it is obvious but entirely insufficient that
they in fact develop a structure in which the parts benefit the
self-preservation of the whole. What matters is rather the reason
why, or the because responsible of this development. The candidate
systems that we know about come into existence in a temporal
process, and the beneficial relation of parts to whole does not
exist prior to that process. The problem is, then, how parts can
initially come to be present
because of their later relation to the whole. The analysis of
teleology does not require this because to be any kind of efficient
causality. But, with
the temporal origin of the
systems we know about, the analysis can be met (Kant argues)
only where a system is the product of design, or some prior
intelligent representation
of the role to be played by the parts.
Further, inner
purposiveness, given that the systems we know about are made of
matter, would then require matter itself to represent ends and
organize itself in accordance—which is impossible (KU 5:383). There
is no evading this argument by returning to a deflationary analysis
which does not constrain the reason why the parts are present, given
cases like the arctic above. So Kant concludes that we cannot know
that any system has true inner purposiveness. We can only think that
a higher form of intellect might have knowledge of “supersensible
real ground of nature” (5:409), and think that this ground might
make possible an inner purposiveness that we could neither
understand nor know.
Hegel will respond in the “Life” chapter at the
conclusion of the Logic.
The chapter’s three sections consider systems meeting three
requirements: systems (i) organized in a manner that supports
self-preservation in the senses of (ii) extracting something needed
from outside itself, and (iii) the reproduction within kind or
species (Gattung).
Hegel agrees with Kant that we do in fact think of organisms, which
meet these criteria, in terms of inner purposiveness. But the key is
that we also take the nature of the reproducing type, kind, or
species as the very substance of the token or individual. And this
species or kind (Hegel argues) would be a distinct teleological form
of “concept” (Begriff).
So inner purposiveness will seem to be an “incomprehensible
mystery”, until and unless we “grasp the concept … as the substance
of life” (WL 6:472/678). For if the kind or concept is the substance
of an organism, then there is a sense in which we can know organisms
to be self-producing: they are the product of something the same in
kind or concept.
And a token part or “member” of such an organism will the product
its own role in the
whole—the product of the beneficial work of its own part (type) in
the whole (type). So this type/token intimacy—the sense in which the
kind is the very substance of the instance—would make such systems
meet Kant’s analysis of inner purposiveness.
Granted,
that we think in such terms about organisms would be no proof
that they are so. But what Hegel shows is that the best reason to
doubt inner purposiveness—Kant’s skeptical argument—in fact supports
it. For Kant’s argument looks to artifacts to establish a demanding
standard for teleology. If Kant says that a gear in a watch is
present because of its
contribution within the whole, then the “its” can refer at once to
the token gear and the
designer’s representation of its
type. And this type-token
intimacy (Hegel shows) establishes real and knowable inner
purposiveness. Strictly speaking, the
Philosophy of Nature
discusses empirical facts about actual living beings; but what is
needed for this Logic
argument will be uncontroversial, since organisms clearly do
assimilate and reproduce.
Hegel’s conclusion is a kind of compatibilism:
Within living beings there is stuff which does what it does because
of its lawful,
non-teleological natures or concepts; there is an “indifference” to
“purpose” (WL 5:482/685). But there is a
further teleological
reason why just such stuff is present in just such an
arrangement—namely, the contribution made to the inner purpose or
telos of
self-preservation. So this defense of natural teleology requires no
claim that all matter as
such is teleological. Nor any claim to know anything like a
supersensible substrate of all matter or nature.
But this is not to say
that Hegel’s view is non-metaphysical or entirely deflationary.
Hegel does not dismiss or unask the metaphysical questions
concerning something over and above the structure of a system or
development—namely, the
reason for this structure or development; he does not, in
particular, mistakenly say that the metaphysical questions could
concern only efficient causes, or only something irrelevant to
teleology.
Hegel’s view is that the metaphysical issues must be faced, but can
be resolved with a case for a metaphysics of immanent concepts that
are teleological, and so a teleological—and normative, in the
associated sense—form of reason in the world.
3. The Idea: Explanatory Completeness
The metaphysics of Hegel’s concept thesis,
however, leave us still short of the extent of his metaphysical
ambitions. For the purposes of understanding these ambitions, we
tend nowadays to worry both too much and also too little about the
kind of metaphysics above. We worry too much in that we overestimate
the threat from fundamentally epistemological concerns, such as the
worry that we could not have knowledge in metaphysics, or that our
concepts in metaphysics have not been (or could not be) shown to
have any genuine relation to objects. Hegel has powerful reasons for
brushing such worries aside: First, such worries should generalize,
affecting equally any other domain: they will be no reason to prefer
epistemology, transcendental reflection, natural science, or
anything else over metaphysics.
For example, taking such worries to require Kantian deductions as
basis for metaphysics would be like, Hegel says, wanting to learn to
swim before getting in the water (§10Anmerk). A second reason for
brushing such concerns aside is that the supposed alternatives to
metaphysics (Hegel argues) are in fact built on metaphysical
assumptions. For example, it is a “fundamental delusion in
scientific empiricism” is that it merely presupposes its own
empiricist metaphysics (§38Anmerk).
But we also worry too little, in that we tend
nowadays to undersestimate the threat from Kant’s Dialectic. Kant’s
argument calls metaphysics generally into question. It does not only
target the metaphysics of otherworldly objects, like immaterial
souls or gods, or the supersensible in that specific sense.
Even a metaphysics of ordinary objects is supposed to involve claims
about the reasons rendering them explicable, and thereby also (at
least implicitly) raising questions about the completeness of such
reasons. But such issues lead to conflicts internal to metaphysics,
even—as in the first two or “mathematical” antinomies—where the
topic is limited to the spatio-temporal
(A530/B558).
Kant’s claim is that the only solution must involve his epistemic
limits, preventing philosophy from answering some questions that it
inescapably raises.
Taking this Kantian worry so seriously is the
basic reason why Hegel needs a systematic metaphysics that relates
everything to the completeness of reason—or “the idea”. To instead
claim to sidestep the worry of the antinomies would be, on Hegel’s
view, a pre-critical reversion from Kant. Thus Hegel, although
following Aristotle on many particulars, also
holds that
everything in metaphysics must be reconstructed, as an organized
whole, on grounds drawn from Kant’s Dialectic. So it is no surprise
that Aristotle is supposed to lack the required systematicity (e.g.
VGP 19:133/2:118).
And Hegel takes the problem to require a
distinctive method in response: We must directly consider incomplete
forms of reason in the world, which trigger antinomy problems. But
we must not conclude that a contrasting completeness of explanation
would be wholly other or beyond this, and knowable or understandable
only by a higher intellect. This would be a kind of “abstract
negation”, as opposed to Hegel’s favored determinate negation.
We must rather draw, out of the problem with incomplete reasons,
incrementally better candidate accounts of more complete forms of
reason.
I turn, then, to Hegel’s account of a form of
incomplete reason, in the “Chemism” chapter.
Hegel is not here addressing what we think of as chemistry
specifically;
he is addressing whatever kinds or concepts fundamentally interact
lawfully.
Hegel argues that to be this kind of thing is
to interact lawfully in certain ways with other kinds; each kind of
lawful thing, then, “is not comprehensible from itself, and the
being of one object is the being of another” (WL 6:430/646). From
here, Hegel quickly reaches a kind of metaphysical holism of the
lawful: to be lawful kind X is to react with Y, and so on to Z and a
whole interconnected network of kinds and laws.
The “determinateness” of anything lawful is just one “moment” of
a larger “whole” or concept of the whole: it “is the concrete moment
of the individual concept of the whole which is the universal
essence, the real kind [Gattung] of the
particular objects” (WL 6:430/646)
The philosophical pressure towards this kind of
metaphysical holism has often been noted more recently, even while
holism is often resisted. Chalmers is an example:
…physical theory only characterizes its basic
entities relationally…
One might be attracted to the view of the world as pure causal flux,
with no further properties for the causation to relate, but this
would lead to a strangely insubstantial view of the physical world.
And there is in
fact a kind of antinomy here. The thesis would demand, as Chalmers
does, that there must be something more to reality than just
relations. The antithesis would deny that there can be anything
more.
To understand Hegel’s response to the problem,
we need to note how he argues throughout earlier parts of the
Logic against the
positing of metaphysical “substrata”. In short, metaphysicians tend
think that substrata in order to support things. But substrata would
(Hegel argues) turn out to be merely “indifferent” (Gleichgültig),
or no form of reason in the world, and no support for anything.
For example, we expect a substratum of any lawful X to be required
to support the possibility of X standing in lawful relations with
any Y. But this appeal would justify, at most, more relations: the
relation of support
between the substratum and X’s relation to Y. The substratum itself
remains indifferent, and no need for support, or any kind of reason,
justifies positing it. The demand for substrata always rests,
rather, on a demand that reality must include something to
correspond to the subject of subject-predicate judgment. This Hegel
takes to be the root of early modern metaphysics of substance,
taking substance to be a kind of “subject” (as in subject-predicate
judgment) that attributes can be “in”. Hegel calls this “the
metaphysics of the understanding”, or of the faculty of judgment.
But, first, such metaphysics provides no justification for the
demand that reality correspond to judgments (EL §28Anmerk).
Furthermore, Hegel argues that the pre-Kantian metaphysics raising
antinomy problems must persist so long as we confuse the demands of
the understanding (for correspondence to the form of judgment) and
of reason (for complete reasons):
The
metaphysics of the past . . . is always on hand, as the
perspective of the
understanding alone on the objects of reason. (EL §27)
Hegel argues that
Kant’s response to the
antinomies is a retreat back to the perspective of the
understanding, which then requires Kant to restrict reason. But
Hegel engages directly with the form of metaphysics considered in
Kant’s Dialectic account of reason, and finds no grounds for letting
the perspective of the understanding stand in the way of resolving
those problems from the perspective of reason alone.
We can now see the distinction between two
kinds of responses in Hegel to worries about the insubstantiality of
lawful reality:
First,
with respect to substrata: Lawful reality is perfectly real—it is
not an illusion—but any lawful X lacks a substratum of lawful
relations with others, and is insubstantial in this respect.
Second,
there is the very different issue of whether there is anything to X
in itself that is a reason why X reacts specifically as it does with
Y, etc. Here Hegel’s response is more complicated. On the one hand,
Hegel again answers in the negative: within the lawful, the search
for the reason proceeds out of X, to Y, and so on, without
completion of the regress. There is no completion even in the whole.
For even the whole web of lawful relations is itself dependent on
there being (“posited”) differentiated parts (WL 4:430/646). This is
a real incompleteness of reason. It is a counter-example to the
rationalists’ PSR.
On the other hand, however, Hegel does see here a real problem—some
truth to the other side of the antinomy problem. For theoretical
inquiry seeks a complete reason, and must presuppose for the sake of
inquiry that there is such a thing. So theoretical inquiry must
conclude that there is at least something else with the determinate
features, lacking in the lawful, which would make for greater
explanatory completeness. This is the systematic ground which
requires the
Logic to turn, after
“Chemism”, towards teleology.
We saw above Hegel’s arguments that teleology
requires inner purposiveness (“Teleology”, the last chapter before
“The Idea” section), and defending inner purposiveness (“Life”, the
first chapter in “The Idea” section). Now we know the point of this
ordering: the inner purposiveness of life first provides any
explanatory completeness. Or, “the idea is,
first of all, life” (WL
6:468/675). To see why, contrast Hegel’s account of a living being
with the explanatory regress of the lawful. Why does a tiger, for
example, have the capacity to catch the deer that it eats? It is not
the case that the only answer is: all that it is to be this kind of
tiger is to catch deer of this kind. Nor is the only answer the one
that would follow the regress into the underlying lawful kinds of
stuff and a network of laws. For there is a kind of explanatory
anchor with the tiger itself: it has claws, and the power to slice,
and this underlying constitution,
because of the
contribution that all this makes to the tiger’s own immanent end of
self-preservation. The inner purposiveness of an organism allows its
nature to be found in the determinate ways that it relates to the
environment, without its nature being merely dissolved away into
external relations. And so it allows for greater explanatory
completeness, and a kind of greater substantiality in this respect.
Thus the Phenomenology
says that an animal is
“the real end [Zweck] itself… [I]t preserves
itself in the relation to
an other” (PhG §256); a lower-level thing “gets lost” (PhG §246).
The Logic says that
“cause” in the sense of “blind necessity” must “pass over into its
other and lose its originality”;
The purpose, by contrast, is posited as
in itself the
determinacy… does not pass over … but instead
preserves itself… (EL
§204Anmerk).
From the account of the immanent purposiveness
of life, then, that we can abstract our way to an understanding of
Hegel’s more general account of explanatory completeness or “the
idea”—and with it his replacement for substrata accounts of the
metaphysics of substance. We need only abstract away from life’s
specific inner purpose of
self-preservation. In general,
only some inner purpose is required. I would express the resulting
theory in this way:
The
idea = a reciprocal process of concept and individual
instances sufficient to establish the concept as the substance of an
individual, and thereby some inner purpose.
So the idea in general requires an account of
a concept with the special relationship to individual instances in
which it gives them their substance. And that is why “the idea”
cannot be understood as only
as one half of that relationship. Thus the canonical formulations of
the material introducing the section titled “The Idea”: “the idea is
the unity of the concept and objectivity” or “the unity of concept
and reality.”
In general, the idea involves
the concept that distinguishes itself from
its objectivity—but an objectivity which is no less determined by it
and possesses its substantiality only in that concept. (WL
6:466/673)
Recall that life is (on Hegel’s account)
something dependent in a
certain respect: life is dependent for its existence on something
underlying with an “indifference … to purpose” (WL 5:482/685), and
so not something interfering with the explanatory completeness of
teleology. This carries several important implications about “the
idea” in general.
First, it means that Hegel is
not arguing that
everything real is just a realization of the idea. The idea, as in
the case of life, is realized in
what is not the idea.
There is reality that is “finite”, specifically in the respect that
it does not involve the above unity of concept and objectivity, or
falls short of the idea. This, Hegel says, is the topic of the
“Objectivity” section prior to “The Idea”:
Finite things are finite because, and to the
extent that, they do not possess the reality of their concept
completely within them but are in need of other things for it… (WL
6:465/672)
Further, Hegel is arguing against a conception
of explanatory completeness as that which is depended upon without
itself being dependent—as something like a substance in the sense of
a substratum. He is aiming for a more positive conception of reason
and its completeness: not in terms of a
lack of dependence, but
in terms of concepts with
explanatory import of their own—a kind of self-determination. If
the latter standard is met, then dependence on an indifferent
substrate does not matter.
And, more radically still, Hegel is arguing not
just that life or this or that actual form of the idea is in fact
dependent; he is arguing for the philosophical conclusion that
anything completely explicable must necessarily be dependent.
Inner purposiveness depends on or is “mediated” by an indifferent,
realizing substrate. The lawful substrate gets lost in relations.
Inner purposiveness must use this substrate. If inner purposiveness
were instead supposed to have a primitive or “immediate” power to
interact with certain chemical substances, then it would itself be
drawn into the mere regress of the lawful, losing its explanatory
completeness:
In an
immediate connection with that object, purpose would itself
enter into the sphere of mechanism and chemism and would therefore
be subject to accidentality and to the loss of its determining
vocation. (WL 6:452/663)
That is why the
idea in general, and not just in the case of life, must be a
process, dependent on there being some substrate indifferent to the
idea, in order to realize the process (WL 6:467–68/674).
On my view, then, there can be no route back
from Hegel’s arguments to a rationalist monism, on which there is a
sufficient reason for everything provided by a substance that is a
substrate in which everything inheres, but itself depends on
nothing. Metaphysics, Hegel argues, cannot rest on any such notion
of substance that it might take as basic, as in the accounts
considered at the end of the “Doctrine of Essence”.
On the contrary, substance too must be reconsidered, accounted for
in terms of “the concept” and ultimately “the idea”, or explanatory
completeness. But to say that the idea is the substance of things
is, again, not to say that it is everything. As we have seen, lawful
reality is insubstantial even though it is real—not a mere
subjective illusion or semblance.
The substantial begins when we come to life. And Hegel’s point
is that all substance must be built out of the insubstantial. This
is one form of the proposal that what is metaphysically prior comes
at the end, and is mediated or dependent on something earlier.
Similarly, “something
has truth only in so far as it is idea” (WL 6:462/670). But
Hegel distinguishes “correctness” from the special notion of “truth”
that he reconstructs in terms of the metaphysics of reason (WL
6:318/562). So, in short: We find
the idea where we have an
inner purpose, and so a normative standard, set by a concept so
intimately related to particular individuals that it gives them
their substance; “truth” is agreement of an object with its own
immanent standard. Some things are not the
idea, having no immanent concept as standard, so there cannot even
be any question of their being “true”. So where “finite things are
finite”, because they do not have concepts providing their very
substance, this is their “untruth”
(WL 6:465/672).
Also similar is Hegel’s claim that we must
“regard everything as being
actual only to the extent that it has the idea in it and
expresses it” (WL 6:464/671). But the term “actual” does not mean
everything that happens to exist; Hegel’s term “discriminates … what
truly merits the name ‘actuality’”
(EL §6). “The actual” (das
Wirkliche) is supposed to be what is effective or what produces
(das Wirkende)
(EL §163Anmerk). Lawfully interacting kinds, for example,
exist but have only the barest trace of borrowed actuality, since
each is an effective reason only on account of relations to
others—they are but the barest trace of the idea. Only full forms of
“the idea” are fully actual.
4. The Absolute Idea, Method, and the Conclusion of the
Logic
There are two especially important openings for
rejoinder. The first concerns Hegel’s metaphysics itself: The
Kantian might object that all this so far concerns only explanatory
completeness that is
relatively greater. But the Transcendental Dialectic is
ultimately concerned with
absolute endpoints of inquiry. Perhaps a Hegelian could respond
that explanatory completeness greater than anything allowed in
Kant’s Antinomies is enough to counter Kant. But Hegel himself
clearly accepts the challenge, seeking to account for the
metaphysics of what he calls “the absolute idea.”
The case of life makes the problem clear,
because there are clearly limits to its explanatory completeness.
There are many different ways in which different species could seek
the end of self-preservation. And the general idea of life does
nothing to explain why
multiple, diverse forms or species should be actually realized
in the world, nor which ones should be; this has no explanation or
reason, on Hegel’s account.
One could imagine that
something more powerful might somehow close those explanatory gaps.
But Hegel’s challenge is provide an explanation of how.
The
Logic’s first proposal, in “The Idea of Cognition”, is that
explanatory completeness might be provided by an individual, X, with
the capacity for theoretical cognition. But if we leave it at that,
then what would do the philosophical work of privileging X would not
be X itself, but rather a special, supposedly higher object beyond
it: “the true” (WL 6:487/697ff.). The same applies to a special
power of willing, and a special supposed object of it, the good (WL
6:541/729ff.). Either way, the metaphysical priority of X would not
be explained, but only presupposed in positing the higher object.
The
Logic’s solution, in
the final chapter, “The absolute Idea”, is this: Go back to the idea
as life and add a sort of thinking
of itself which (Hegel
argues) thereby makes the immanent purpose no longer
self-preservation but
rather a sort of freedom.
So:
The
absolute idea = any reciprocal process of concept or kind and
individual where thinking or reflection establishes freedom
as immanent purpose.
The freedom here is
a sense in which realizations of this concept would be not merely
determined by that concept—their substance—behind their back, as it
were; such a case would be what it is because its concept or
Begriff would not just be
in itself, in that last
sense, but also for itself.
So, relative to the initial proposals about the good and the
true, the Logic needs “a
turning back to life”,
but without the “immediacy” of life or its lack of the
for itself. This is
supposed to make possible a variety of “the idea” which now, unlike
life, explains diversity out of itself, or “harbors the most extreme
opposition within” (WL 6:548/735). And this absolute idea is what
just what was missing in “Life”: “the
free kind [Gattung]
for itself” (EL §222).
Now one
illustration of the gist here will come later in the
Encyclopedia, with the
theory of spirit. There we will get a case that the concept or
Begriff of human beings
is freedom, and that this explains from itself, first, the emergence
of conflict and so diversity in the way in which human beings
organize themselves, and, second, a kind of directionality to our
development toward forms of social life that realize freedom.
But for the Logic,
nothing specifically about
human beings as such matters. What is important is rather the
case of whatever might
think through the argument of the
Logic itself. So the
Logic distinguishes the
topic that “belongs to the doctrine of spirit proper” from “[t]he
idea of spirit which is
the subject matter of logic”,
or “the logical idea of spirit” (WL 6:496/695–96). Spirit (in this
logical sense) is what thinks, and so entangles itself in the
problems of philosophy, and in this way generates from itself the
distinctions between different steps along the way of the
Logic, until it comes to the conclusion that its kind or concept
is a free thinking which realizes the absolute idea. If we can think
through this process, then the absolute idea is real.
This is also what Hegel means in emphasizing
the definite articles in the
idea (die Idee), and
the concept (der
Begriff).
There are many forms of concept, but others turn out to be
lesser forms of the absolute case of
the concept, the concept
of freedom: “The concept is the free, as the substantial
power that is for itself” (EL §160). And all forms of the idea
are lesser forms of this absolute form: “the idea” is “the free
concept, the concept determining itself and thereby determining
itself as reality” (EL §213Anm).
And this is
what is meant by Hegel’s famous claims that substance must be
understood as subject or spirit.
The point is not to accept Spinoza’s claim that there is a single
substance/substrate “in” which everything real inheres, adding only
that this is a subject or spirit. For Hegel’s absolute idea is no
substrate at all. Nor is it an individual. It is a process or
movement, and one connecting a universal kind and particular
individuals. And Hegel denies that everything real is just a form of
the absolute idea, holding that this process is realized in
something not the absolute idea, or spirit in the logical sense.
But there is a second obvious opening for
rejoinder. And this is now a distinctive form of
epistemological problem
raised by Hegel’s metaphysics. In short, the issues raised in Kant’s
Dialectic concern, on Kant’s account, the ideas of reason as guiding
theoretical inquiry. Hegel responds with a metaphysics on which it
is not the case that everything truly realizes the absolute idea.
But from Kant’s point of view, then, the guidance of reason would
seem to leave inquiry on some domains, such as that of the lawful,
simply hopeless—in that it could not possibly reach its guiding
goal.
Note, however, that Kant faces a similar
problem. On Kant’s view, we can never reach knowledge of anything
unconditioned. Why then is inquiry not hopeless? Kant argues that
our inquiry can at least make progress, heading in the direction
that would, if we could follow completely, satisfy
reason—progressing “asymptotically, as it were, i.e., merely by
approximation” (A663/B691).
Now reconsider the problem for Hegel: True,
Hegel’s metaphysics allows the lawful neither to be nor to
metaphysically depend upon the absolute idea. Still, Hegel’s account
opens up a different way of accounting for the
epistemological side of
explanation—the sense in which finding explanations should produce
insight into or
understanding of the
world.
For explaining in lawful cases could produce such understanding in
virtue of an approximation of the lawful, for example, to the
absolute idea. So even chemism falls short in way shown, in the
Logic, to suggest the
right direction, or being on the way: chemism “is not yet for itself
that totality of self-determination” (WL 6:429/645).
In the end, then, Hegel advocates two different
forms of the priority of the absolute idea:
Metaphysical priority: the absolute idea is the absolutely
complete form of reason in the world, and so prior in a metaphysics
of reason.
Epistemological priority: all intelligibility of everything
depends on the intelligibility of the absolute idea.
If “idealism”
refers to any claim for a priority of any form of idea or mind, then
these are both a metaphysical and an epistemological form of
“idealism”. The latter view is also a form of epistemological
monism, because it requires that the intelligibility of anything
requires its fitting a system of knowledge that would relate
everything to the absolute idea. The conclusion of the
Logic gives this
epistemological monism a striking formulation in claiming that “the
method” discussed here is that of theoretical inquiry generally. The
point is this: In pursuing theoretical inquiry on some domain we are
seeking the rational or the absolute idea there. We can reach
explanatory satisfaction to different degrees on different domains.
But no limit here is an epistemic limit of ours; it would stem from
the metaphysical incompleteness of some domains. And whatever
satisfaction we reach anywhere will be only in finding there at
least an approximation of the idea. Finding laws of nature would be
one step in a process
that, if carried farther through,
would have to turn into an inquiry looking very different on the
surface: it would have to find in its results contradictions, which
point to something more complete, until we come to the absolute idea
thinking itself. There is supposed to be a natural progression here
from what would begin as empirical, and end up a priori in
the sense that the method in the Logic and its results would
be independent regardless of any initiating empirical details. So
physics may be complete relative to its own purposes, but it
also raises further questions that reason cannot ignore.
Thus, the Logic pursues
…the method proper to each and every
fact… It is therefore not only the highest force of reason,
or rather its sole and absolute force,
but also reason’s highest and sole impulse to find
and recognize itself through itself in all things. (WL
6:551–52/737)
Note the way in which this explains Hegel’s
famous claims about circular structure: Philosophy itself is a form
of rational inquiry; so it seeks the end of reason, or complete
reason in the world.
Thus it must necessary begin by at least by presupposing, for the
sake of inquiry, that three is some complete form of reason to be
sought. The Logic’s final
account of the absolute idea and philosophical method is supposed to
justify (and in this sense
mediate) that initially unjustified (or immediate)
presupposition:
By virtue of the nature of the method just
indicated, the science presents itself as a circle that winds
around itself, where the mediation winds the end back to the
beginning. (WL 6:571/751)
But the point here
crucially concerns epistemic
necessity. There is no claim for the existence of the rationalists’
metaphysically necessary substance, a subject containing the
predicate of existence, as a beginning or ground on which everything
depends. Rather, the point is that the beginning is not arbitrary,
but a standpoint necessary
for philosophy as a form of theoretical inquiry; and this
must lead, through
contradictions, to their resolution with the absolute idea.
Finally, this overall argument of the
Logic is supposed to
establish a kind of “absolute knowledge.” The point is that there is
no in-principle limit to our access to explanatory knowledge. So the
view is not that we can know every fact all at once—let alone just
by reading the Logic.
We can through reading the
Logic gain knowledge of a form of absolute idea—of spirit, in
the logical sense involving thinking through the
Logic itself; this is
knowledge of “the concept
that comprehends itself
conceptually” (WL 6:572/752). And in all other cases that fall
short of this, including the rotation of matter in the solar system
and the growth of living beings, also generate contradictions that
connect consideration of them back up with the absolute and the case
of spirit. This need not include a supposed explanation for anything
like a complete reason for the location and features of every
material particle in the universe. For Hegel denies that there is
always complete explanation for everything, leaving no reasons
unknowable where there are no reasons. Still, whatever follows and
comprehends the path of the
Logic can know itself as
spirit in the logical sense and the absolute idea. Thus, Hegel
says, where he glosses the point to be made in the last chapter of
the Logic:
spirit recognizes the idea as its
absolute truth . . . the
infinite idea . . . which is the absolute knowledge of itself. (WL
6:469/675)
Conclusion
We can now consider the bearing of this
material, from the conclusion of the
Logic, on other recently
popular interpretative approaches to Hegel. I have many debts to
members of all of the groups I will mention, which I have tried to
note above. But I have argued that understanding the end of the
Logic requires rejecting
a point on which most everyone seems to agree, namely: Hegel’s
engagement internally with Kant’s philosophy need not (and does not)
involve taking as a basis any broadly epistemological concerns, from
Kant or otherwise. Some, a first group, think that Hegel fails to so
engage with epistemological concerns, and so begs the question
against Kant; they usually take Hegel to be a metaphysical monist.
Others think that Hegel does manage to argue from epistemological
considerations. Some, a second ground, think that he gives an
epistemological argument for metaphysical monism. For example,
knowledge would require no gap between subject and object, which
would both have to be in the One.
Others still, a third group, see Hegel as basing his project on more
deflationary epistemological considerations, arguing for an
epistemological fallibilism and/or coherentism, which is supposed to
lead to a more modest form of ontological holism.
It is worth saying something more about a
fourth kind of approach, descendent from Pippin’s breakthrough
Hegel’s Idealism (1989).
Of the alternatives, this best captures something I think crucial:
the way Hegel’s project draws its considerable philosophical
strengths from the way it is unified by a metaphilosophical
commitment, about what is
basic in philosophy. But, compared to my proposals above, this
Kantian account sees the opposite metaphilosophical details: Hegel
is supposed to take as “basic to his project” issues with a unifying
“common theme”—“the argument that any subject must be able to make
certain basic discriminations in any experience in order for there
to be experience at all” (1989, 7-8). More recent versions might
substitute for “experience” a concern with conditions of the
possibility of any relation between concept and object, of the
normativity of concept use, of objective purport, etc. All such
versions agree that Hegel’s project aims to extend Kant’s positive
project from the Transcendental Analytic. It is a mistake to object
that this Kantian approach precludes recognition of Hegel as
metaphysician, or limits Hegel to subjective idealism. The Kantian
approach can allow Hegel to pursue metaphysics, so long as
metaphysics itself is understood through the lens of issues
descended from Kant’s Analytic being basic. And one might argue that
Hegel seeks, by accounting for the conditions of the possibility of
cognition, to account for
objects of cognition themselves, and even to eliminate any
Kantian worries about any unknowability of objects in themselves;
one might argue that this is a kind of metaphysics.[49]
But while I see how one might get
a metaphysics in this
way, it doesn’t seem to me to be
the metaphysics of the end of
the Logic. Consideration of the possibility of cognition of any
object might get you a metaphysics of what is common to all objects.
Or it might get you a metaphysical priority of one side of a dualism
over the other: of the judging
subject over the
objects of its judgments.
But I don’t see how it could get you Hegel’s tight focus on a
metaphysics of reason, so
clearly suggested by borrowing the crucial
terminology
here—“the idea”, “reason”, etc.—specifically from Kant’s Dialectic.
And I don’t see how it could get you Hegel’s complex
development of multiple steps of metaphysical priority of reasons in
the world. For example, Hegel’s point about the inner purposiveness
of life is not that every
object is alive in the full sense, nor that this is necessary
condition of the possibility of judgment about any object. The
metaphysical priority of teleological to non-teleological forms of
reason in the world is crucial. Nor is the point that anything with
inner purposiveness would engage in acts of judgment or cognition in
the full sense. A metaphysical priority of the absolute idea over
the idea generally is also crucial. Perhaps the Kantian deduction
approach, if focusing specifically on the end of the
Logic,
would best argue that any
“object-level” metaphysical ambitions here are not “playing any
significant role in the position defended”, which is more
“metalevel” (Pippin 1989, 247). But the arguments themselves in this
stretch of text, I have tried to show, do have such direct
metaphysical import—as for example about objects structured by inner
purposiveness.
True, Hegel engages even here with
epistemological problems, but he does so specifically as these are
radically reshaped by his taking the metaphysics of reason as more
fundamental; this is why the epistemological issues come to be those
raised specifically by Hegel’s metaphysics of explanation—concerning
the possibility of intelligibility or understanding, in that sense,
rather than anything like relations between acts of cognition or
judgment and objects of cognition or judgment. That is why I think
it better to place the considerable insights of the Kantian approach
in context of the opposite reading of Hegel’s unifying aims.
Sticking to the Kantian deduction approach, at this point, would
seem to require a transition principle. For example, one might see a
basis in a deduction of a
priori necessary conditions of intelligibility, and then
transition by means of a principle requiring that anything real must
be intelligible. But that principle defines the rationalism Kant’s
Dialectic rejects; and Hegel follows, taking Kant’s “insight into
the necessary conflict” to leave
that sort of metaphysics
hopeless, a reversion from the “loftier spirit of modern philosophy”
(WL 5:38-9/25-6). The modern options would then be
either Kant’s
restrictions or Hegel’s
reconstruction of metaphysics on grounds from Kant’s Dialectic. If
the latter works, then it leaves no support for Kant’s attempt to
transform metaphysics by placing it on the basis of deductions like
those of the Transcendental Analytic. And this is why I think that
the real Hegel is in a philosophically stronger position than either
any either Kantianized or epistemologized Hegel could be: the real
Hegel needs no transition principle from any supposed basis to
metaphysics; rather, Logic
knocks out other options until concluding that theoretical
philosophy should always already be direct engagement with the
metaphysics of reason.
Finally, I think that the conclusion of the
Logic is philosophically
strong enough to suggest the lasting importance of some questions
relatively neglected today. First, consider those today who would
prefer to pursue a version of Kant’s transformed theoretical
philosophy, taking as basic to their projects broadly
epistemological issues about the relation of cognition and objects.
But why? To judge by Hegel, the attractive option here will not be
any claim that metaphysics is a matter of indifference. Kant already
sees this as hopeless (Ax). And if metaphysics is not a matter of
indifference, then how to justify the broadly Kantian
transformation? Hegel shows that no arguments from a broadly
epistemological basis; they would presume the authority or
fundamentality of epistemology in trying to defend it. So even
though Kant’s Dialectic is relatively neglected today, reading Hegel
suggests that it is what
should be most crucial for Kantians today. Can contemporary Kantians
defend the Dialectic argument itself? Or can they replace it with
some new way of arguing that metaphysics goes awry from within?
Second, consider those who would still pursue
metaphysics today. To judge by Hegel, the attractive option here is
not to dismiss all
worries about metaphysics as irrelevant because merely
epistemological. For Hegel shows that even fans of metaphysics
should recognize the importance of very different challenges like
those of Kant’s Dialectic. And Hegel’s response suggests an
essential question here about metaphysical foundationalism. As
contemporary philosophy turns back toward metaphysics, it develops
just as Kantians and Hegelians should expect: it begins to focus on
metaphysical conditions—like
the “grounds” now considered under the heading of “metaphysical
grounding”; and then it begins to focus on forms of the
unconditioned, ultimate grounds, and new forms of what is now called
“metaphysical foundationalism”.
The question suggested by the conclusion of Hegel’s
Logic is
whether metaphysics can defend some form of foundationalism
against the problems raised by Kant’s Dialectic and Hegel? Or is it
better for metaphysicians to seek, with Hegel, a principled
alternative to metaphysical foundationalism?
In any case, the end of Hegel’s
Logic shows that his
basic aim is to rebuild metaphysics on grounds of the strongest
worry about it. Because of this, he can still help us to engage with
one another philosophically, even across the chasm separating those
who would travel in contrasting philosophical directions. For Hegel
offers us a single metaphilosophical framework that can bring into
focus at once both powerful worries about metaphysics, and also
continuing prospects for its defense.
end
[1] E.g.
A307/B364. I defend Kant’s argument on this score in my
2015, ch. 4. For other accounts in terms of
explanation see
Grier (2001, 145); Allison (2004, 331) and Rohlf (2010,
206). And see Proops (2010, 455) on Kant’s focus on worldly
“conditions” or “grounds”, and the connection to
why-questions.
[2] See
my 2008a on the connection to the PSR.
On metaphysics
and unanswerable questions, see the A-Preface to the
Critique. My
formulation saves room for other contexts aside from such
philosophy, including practical contexts, in which we have
(Kant holds) justification for conclusions about the
unconditioned.
There may be
other great differences between projects taking the narrowly
epistemological or the semantic as fundamental. Still, the
project concluding at the end of the
Logic, is (I
argue) neither.
See e.g. Kant
on the importance of doubt about metaphysics at Proleg 4:256
Kant notes the
need for support from the Dialectic at Bxix.
[7] See
e.g. §24, and similar at WL 5:45; VPG 7:23 and 422; VGP
18:369, 19:262. On this point I follow Horstmann (e.g. 1991,
175ff.) and Beiser (e.g. 2003), but draw conclusions both
would reject.
For example,
Hegel says that the
first two parts of the
Logic (the
“objective logic”), rather than its actual conclusion, are
comparable to Kant’s “transcendental logic” (WL
5:58-62/40-43).
[9] With
respect to the notion that objects are what they are owing
to their “concept”, nature or form, it is essential to note
Westphal (1989, ch. 10) and Stern (1990); I am greatly
indebted to them. On this topic, see also my (2007)
and (2008). But I will also diverge from Stern and Westphal
in many other ways below.
Respectively,
VGP 19:319/2:297 and PhG §321.
This allows
another side, with any number of other constraints on
explanation that are epistemic, contextual, etc.
Compare
Inwood’s reading on which
Hegel does sometimes require such a premise (1983, 63–4).
VPG 12:23/34.
Hegel here glosses a view Anaxagoras “was the first” to
hold; Hegel adopts the view but puts it to his own very
different purposes.
In effect,
whatever the role for subjective purposes is, purposive
agents acting on mechanistic objects would also require
bodies that are organized teleologically independent of
subjective purposes. See also Pippin (1991, 245) and de
Vries (1991, 57–8).
The concept
of a Naturzweck
is “problematic,” so that when employing it “one does not
know whether one is judging about something or nothing” (KU
5:397). Also EE 20:234 and KU 5:396. On KU on teleology in I
follow here my 2005 and 2013.
“[P]arts …
are possible only through their relation to the whole” (KU
5:373). See also Kant’s stress on the because—darum
and weil—in
arguing that benefit is not enough (KU 5:369).
Kant’s
formulation folds the two requirements together: the parts
must be “combined into a whole by being reciprocally the
cause and effect of their form” (KU 5:373).
See KU 5:372
and Zuckert 2007, 136.
I follow my
2008 on this material.
“A. The
Living Individual”, “B. The Life Process”, and “C. Kind (Gattung)”
respectively.
“[T]he
realized species (Gattung)”
here “ has posited itself as identical with the concept” (WL
6:486/688).
See for
example Hegel on Aristotle: “That which is produced is as
such in the ground, that is, it is an end, kind [Gattung]
in itself, it is by the same token prior, before it becomes
actual, as potentiality. Man generates men; what the product
is, is also the producer” (VGP 19:176).
See Yeomans,
ChX for a similar point applied to Hegel’s philosophy of
action: the retrospective element of Hegel’s theory is not
the whole; Hegel recognizes a “productive relation between
the agent and her action”, so that traditional problems
about free will must be engaged rather than dismissed.
See for
example Hegel’s reply to empiricist attempts to use
skepticism against metaphysics (§39Anmerk).
Contrast
Beiser (2003, 55).
For example,
on responding to the Antinomies with “abstract negation” (WL
6:562–3/745).
On this
chapter, I follow my 2008b.
“Both,
mechanism as well as chemism, are … included under natural
necessity” (WL 6:438/652).
1996, 153.
Compare also Russell (1927, 325).
For example,
WL 6:307–8/554–55.
Note also
Hegel’s explicit criticisms of the PSR at (WL 6:82–83/388).
On the sense
in which this leaves contradiction in the world, see my
(2015, ch 6).
WL 6:464/671 and 6:466/673, respectively.
See also Ng
ChY and Zambrana ChZ on Hegel’s critique of Spinoza and its
role in the transition from “Substance” at the end of “The
Doctrine of Essence” to “The Doctrine of the Concept”.
See Kitcher’s
(1986) and my (2009) alternative account of this.
That
explanation has a metaphysical side, emphasized above, does
not preclude it from also having this epistemological side.
Compare Kim (1994).
See EL
8:13/pp. 6–7 and 8:38/p. 26.
Cf. “it is
quite improper” to try to “deduce” the “contingent products
of nature” (EN §250anm).
E.g.,
Guyer (1993, 171–72); Dusing (1976, 119; 1983, 421); Siep
(2000, 18–21).
E.g.,
Beiser (1993, 15). Horstmann sees in Hegel an argument
resting on epistemology, but not a primary interest in
epistemology (2006, 23). I think that the correctness and
importance of his latter point justifies denying the former,
and revising our understanding of the metaphysics itself.
E.g.
Westphal (1989, ch. 10) and Stern (2009).
[49] See
Pippin’s use of Kant’s A158/B197 both at 1989, 33 and, more
recently, 2014, 148.
Perhaps by
way of Pippin’s powerful (1987) argument that Kant’s own
epistemology pushes against Kant’s claim to metaphysical
neutrality, towards a robust metaphysics of the spontaneity
of the subject.
See
especially Schaffer’s (2010, 37) defense of monism on
grounds of foundationalism.