Aristotelian Priority, Metaphysical Definitions of God, and Hegel on
Pure Thought as Absolute
James Kreines - jkreines@cmc.edu
Final draft; please cite from the published version in the Hegel Bulletin.
Abstract: This paper advances a philosophical interpretation of Hegel’s
Logic as defending a metaphysics, which includes an absolute, itself
comparable to God in other systems of metaphysics of interest to Hegel,
including Aristotle’s and Spinoza’s. Two problems are raised which can seem
to block the prospects for such a metaphysically inflationary
interpretation. The key to resolving these problems is consideration of the
kinds of metaphysical priority that Hegel sees in Aristotle. This allows us
to build a philosophical model of Hegel’s absolute, and to demonstrate how
the model fits the argument of Hegel’s Logic. Application of this
model provides a philosophical explanation of the senses in which Hegel’s
metaphysics is idealist; he argues that thought is absolute, and comparable
to God in other systems of metaphysics: thought is both self-determining and
metaphysically prior to being.
Hegel’s
Science of Logic focuses on
“logical determinations”, and the Encyclopaedia version explains that these
“can be regarded as the definitions of the absolute, as metaphysical
definitions of God” (EL:
§85). Such formulations are not unusual; the self-standing
Logic compares its topic to “the
logical course of God’s self-determination as being” (WL:
627/12:129).
Hegel sees “definitions of the absolute” or “of God” in many other
metaphysicians, emphasizing cases including Spinoza’s
Ethics and Aristotle’s
Metaphysics.
Given passages like the above, I think an interpretation of Hegel would be
the better, all else equal, if it can make sense of the
Logic as a defence of an absolute
that is comparable to these other
cases.
By
“comparable”, I mean neither total agreement nor the sense in which any two
things are comparable in some respect. Rather, I mean two specific respects.
The first concerns the relation of the absolute to the non-absolute: the
absolute has metaphysical priority;
the non-absolute metaphysically
depends on the absolute, in some Hegelian sense to be determined, and
without reciprocation. Spinoza is comparable: the modes depend, in Spinoza’s
sense of being “in” and “conceived through”, God or the one substance (e.g.
E1P15D), without God reciprocally depending on the modes.
The second
respect concerns the relation of the absolute to itself: The absolute will
be, in some Hegelian sense to be specified,
self-determining. I think that
Hegel sees something comparable in Aristotle, in interpreting the
Metaphysics as defending an
“absolute” or God “whose essence is pure activity” (VGP: 2:143/158).
Spinoza’s specific sense of the comparable point is that God is supposed to
be “the cause of itself” (e.g. E1P7D). (Hegel’s will be, we will see, a
metaphysics built around
self-determination, rather than
priority, but does include the
latter.)
Some may
expect that trying to make philosophical sense of Hegel’s conclusions and
arguments, in the spirit above, requires giving a deflationary
interpretation—either a non-metaphysical interpretation, or a metaphysical
interpretation that does not include an absolute that is self-determining
and metaphysically prior. Indeed, much recent work—Stern (1990, 2009) is in
an important case—approaches Hegel via Aristotle, as I will here, with
deflationary aims.
My aim in this small paper is not any final reckoning of costs and benefits
of other approaches, let alone the interpretation of interpreters that this
would require. My aim is to show the possibility of a surprising path toward
a non-deflationary reading,
recognizing Hegel’s metaphysical absolute and its self-determination and
priority, which brings significant benefits and without incurring the costs
that might be expected.
I should
add before beginning that, in orienting via passages about “God” or the
absolute, I have not the remotest interest in partisan defence (or attack
on) religion. The
Logic forbids arguments from
revealed religion. Here I take the metaphysics to be independently
interesting, and pursue it as such.
Further, I
will argue from some specific
claims, of Hegel’s, about
Aristotle, selected for their usefulness in solving philosophical and
interpretive problems. I neither argue for my own reading of Aristotle, nor
ask how best to grasp the whole of Hegel’s interpretation of Aristotle.
I. Two basic problems about Hegel
There are,
admittedly, problems that seem to block the direction I would like to take
towards a philosophical explanation of Hegel’s absolute and the two senses
of combability. But once we articulate these, we can see that they are not
special problems given my aims, but problems for interpreters generally.
They are:
1. The
problem about the meaning or content of Hegel’s desired conclusions. Hegel
makes claims about an absolute. But Hegel makes two other commitments that
seem doomed to be philosophically incompatible with this:
1.A. The
first facet of this problem concerns Hegel’s
anti-dualism. To begin with an
example, some philosophers would distinguish
thought from
being; they might then hold one
metaphysically prior to the other, and hold it to be absolute. Hegel’s view
is a kind of metaphysical idealism, so it would be unsurprising for his
metaphysics to fall closer to holding thought to be absolute, and
metaphysically prior to being. The problem, however, is understanding what
this could mean, given that the anti-dualist Hegel claims that being is not
ultimately distinct from thought, that there is a unity between them, etc.
Insofar as
the point applies to any supposed dualism between some X and Y, anti-dualism
seems to undercut the distinction and so push to a deflationary denial that
anything is metaphysically prior to anything else, and so that anything is
absolute. And it is no solution to just appeal at the end of the day,
without further explanation, to opaque, Hegelian-seeming formulations like:
X is Y, but X is also not Y.
The
problem for me here is that my aim of making sense of the metaphysical
priority of absolute over non-absolute, in Hegel, can seem destined to pay a
cost in conflicting with Hegel’s anti-dualism. But this is a problem for
everyone, because anyone who
takes anti-dualism as reason for a deflationary reading seems equally
destined to pay a cost relative to Hegel’s claims about metaphysical
definitions of God or an absolute. What I argue below is that there is a
non-deflationary reading that pays no cost here, but instead solves the
problem, explaining the compatibility of anti-dualism and the metaphysical
priority of an absolute over the non-absolute.
1.B.
Thoroughgoing mediation: Hegel
holds that everything is “mediated”, so that nothing is entirely
“immediate”. Hegel applies this commitment within epistemology, as noted
above, to rule out the above philosophical appeal to supposedly purely
immediate forms of knowledge, not
mediated by any need of justification.
And he applies it in metaphysics, making everything metaphysically mediated,
dependent or conditioned in some respect—even
the absolute. Here are some cases of that application: First, consider
Hegel’s formulation in terms of his idea of a “true infinity”: “finitude” is
mediated, and non-absolute (WL: 124/21:142); but the “true infinite”
is also mediated, specifically by
the finite: “[T]he infinite is only as the transcending of the finite” (WL:
116/21:133). Second, Hegel famously argues that metaphysical systems trying
to make their absolute into something purely
immediate end up with an
absolute so indeterminate as to amount to nothing (EL: §86–7).
Third, in criticizing Spinoza’s metaphysics, Hegel says that “the absolute
cannot be a first, an immediate”, but is a “result” (WL: 473/11.376).
The
problem, then, is this: if everything is on a metaphysical par in this
respect of dependence or mediation, then this again seems to push in the
deflationary direction, making it hard to see how anything in Hegel’s
metaphysics could be distinguished in being absolute, and especially
absolute in the two senses of comparability.
Some think
that a view they take to be holist, and deflationary, leaves no problem
here. They see Hegel as holding that each thing depends on its wider
context, and so on until, but only until we reach the comprehensive whole of
everything, at which point questions about what this whole depends on, or is
explained by, become meaningless, leaving it absolute in not being
dependent.
I think this remains problematic: First, this seems merely a
default sense of absoluteness;
something is absolute not because of anything about
it but because of the
lack of something somewhere else
to condition it—as opposed to Hegel’s above-noted self-determination of the
absolute. Second, and
regardless of that problem, this
kind of metaphysics is not really in keeping with Hegel’s
thoroughgoing mediation, because
it still denies that the absolute/whole is dependent. Hegel holds that
everything is mediated, even the
absolute, the infinite, etc. This
seems to push toward “holism”, as I will use the term, in the specific sense
that dependence is exhausted by everything—including
both whole and parts—being
equally mutually dependent. And that brings us back to the problem: If
everything is equally dependent, then how then could anything be absolute?
Or, if there is an absolute, then how could everything be metaphysically
dependent?
2. Even if
we can in the end make philosophical sense of the meaning of Hegel’s desired
conclusions, the second problem is that there appears to be good reason to
think he cannot possibly give a philosophical argument for them.
To begin
with, note that Hegel sees Parmenides and Spinoza as resting the weight of
their arguments on the principle that
nothing comes from nothing. Spinoza takes himself to follow Descartes in
thinking of this as a demand that everything requires a cause or a reason.
For concision and clarity, I follow contemporary usage in using Leibniz’s
name, “principle of sufficient reason”, or just “PSR”, noting that neither
Hegel nor Spinoza uses this terminology.
Sometimes the PSR is expressed in the form:
there are no brute facts, or
nothing is brute. In any case,
the problem arises because there is much in Hegel that seems to require him
to deny this principle, for example:
First,
Hegel’s metaphysics includes what I call
incomplete explicables. For
example, in nature there is supposed to be series of levels extending from
the less completely explicable,
for example mechanical phenomena, to the relatively more completely
explicable, in the case of life.
But any degree of lack of completeness of explicability would seem to
violate the PSR, or mean that there is in such phenomena something that
lacks any reason, comes from nothing, etc.
Second,
Hegel argues that the PSR forces
Spinoza toward a conclusion that Hegel rejects. More specifically, the
principle supporting Spinoza’s monism would (Hegel argues) also rule out a
cause or reason for the existence of anything either finite or determinate,
forcing Spinoza to eliminate the latter. God would then be a “dark,
shapeless abyss, as it were, that swallows up into itself every determinate
content” (EL: §151Z). This contributes to Hegel’s conclusion that ‘spinozism
is a deficient philosophy” (WL: 472/11:376). Crucially, it is the
principle itself that forces the direction Hegel resists:
Ex nihilo,
nihil fit…
nothing comes from nothing… Those who zealously hold firm to the proposition
… are unaware that in so doing they are subscribing to the abstract
pantheism of the Eleatics and essentially also to that of Spinoza. (WL:
61/5:85)
This seems to be a clear rejection of the principle.
Another
way to see the problem is to note the way in which attempts to locate
arguments in Hegel’s metaphysics seem to commit him to the PSR. For example,
Beiser sees Hegel as arguing that the Hegelian absolute is a condition of
the possibility of knowledge or experience. But if we have no PSR, then it
would be at least as reasonable, rather than positing an absolute, to just
say that knowledge and experience
are among those things not completely explicable—so that they could just
be, in a brute fashion, requiring
no ground or condition to explain their possibility.
Similarly,
Inwood sees Hegel as arguing against a metaphysics of forces, because this
is supposed to leave an explanatory gap between forces and the phenomena to
be explained (1983: 63). But if we have no PSR, then it would seem to be at
least as reasonable, instead of heading in the direction of any Hegelian
absolute, to make do with a metaphysics of forces and hold that forces just
do have certain brute effects.
Inwood is
an interesting case because he sees Hegel as equivocal about the principle
required by the argument (as Inwood reads it): as “believing, or at least
half-believing, that everything had to be just as it is and that it could be
shown why it is so” (1983: 64). And perhaps half-belief in a needed
premise is why Inwood elsewhere
sees Hegel as half-believing his own
conclusion about an absolute (as Inwood reads this): Hegel “believed, or
at any rate half-believed, that the world was a product of pure thought,
that God or reason was in the world, and so on” (1983: 1).
I think we
should take the seeming
half-beliefs as problems, seeking philosophical explanation of a
wholehearted conclusion (problem 1), and the principle (2) on which it
rests. If we do not solve these basic problems, then Hegel will seem almost
everywhere ambivalent or even ‘schizophrenic”.
Even if we try to ignore the Logic
and/or the absolute, and look to Hegel on natural science, or human
history, for example—the familiar problems there, pushing us in seemingly
incompatible inflationary and deflationary directions, can now be seen as
reflections of the underlying problems above. We should not see the problems
as reason to give up trying to make sense of Hegel’s absolute and the two
senses of comparability. They are problems for Hegel interpreters more
generally. The big question is what interpretive response has the best
combination of costs and benefits. In the rest of this paper I argue that
there is a surprising path forwards, focused on the self-determination and
metaphysical priority of the absolute, that has surprising benefits relative
to the problems.
II. Priority with reciprocal dependence à la
Aristotle
Our
problems extend, then, to even understanding Hegel’s conclusions, regardless
of the argument for them. Here it can help to begin with a kind of
combination view that Hegel adopts and sees in Aristotle’s
Metaphysics. I should note that
Hegel’s adoption of the positions discussed in this section is approximate,
because it will be qualified by his idealism; I will not continue to state
the need for qualification, but return to it.
I begin
with the combination in the specific case of the relation of a substantial
form to a hylomorphic compound; here I think it can be understood, also by
non-Hegelians, how the former might be metaphysically both prior and yet
also dependent.
In what
sense prior? Hegel thinks that
the form “human being”, for example,
makes a particular human being what she is, and the reverse is not the
case. Hegel’s statements of this position incorporate much else that is less
important at this moment: his treatment of Aristotle’s substantial form as
universal, contrasting to
individuals of that form;
and his idealist terminology, to be discussed later, labelling the
form/universal also as “concept” (Begriff).
But for now the point is just the kind of priority involved in substantial
forms (however further conceived). Hegel says:
…the
nature, the specific
essence … is the
concept of the thing,
the universal which is present in it
just as there is present in each human being, although universally
unique, a specific principle that
makes him human … there is no saying what such an individual could still be
if this foundation were removed from him … The indispensable foundation, the
concept, the universal … (WL:
16–7/21:15)
The priority is clear: form/universal/concept makes the individual what it
is, and not vice versa. This is not
just Hegel; it is a familiar option, at the very least, to see this
priority in Aristotle. Proponents might look to passages like this:
…why is
this individual thing, or this body in this state, a man? …what we seek is
the cause, i.e. the form, by reason of which the matter is some definite
thing; and this is the substance of the thing… (Metaphysics:
1041b)
On the
other hand, Hegel also sees in Aristotle, and adopts, a sense in which such
a substantial form is nonetheless
dependent or mediated. Here
the specific dependence is that the form/universal/concept “exists” only as
the “nature” of individuals, and not something that could exist itself
without individuals. Hegel says:
The
animal as such cannot be shown,
only a specific animal can. The
animal does not exist [existiert
nicht] but is instead the
universal nature of individual animals… (EL:
§24Z1)
The language mirrors Aristotle’s familiar criticisms of the more Platonist
view: “they say there is a man-in-himself and a horse-in-itself and
health-in-itself, with no further qualification” (Metaphysics:
997b). This is, again, not
just Hegel; it is a familiar option, at least, to associate such
dependence with Aristotle, and with Hegel as well.
But how
could priority and dependence fit together coherently? To answer, we need to
specify the two different ways of thinking about dependence and priority. I
do so in a manner influenced by recent work on Aristotle, and marked with
terminology from Schelling’s reading of Hegel. I will call this a
distinction between issues concerning
what something is and issues concerning
that it is.
To begin with the latter, one way in which Aristotle thinks about priority
is to consider as prior things “which can be without other things, while the
others cannot be without them—a
distinction which Plato used” (Metaphysics:
1019a). Or: that there are
X’s depends on that there are
Y’s, and not vice-versa. I will borrow from Beere’s formulations of the idea
in Aristotle (2008), but pry apart the dependence from the associated
priority. So:
Y
that-depends on X iff Y could not be if X were not.
If the dependence is not reciprocated, we have something prior:
X is
that-prior to Y iff Y that-depends on X, and not
vice versa.
What we have in Hegel on the dependence of substantial form, above, is the
claim that substantial form that-depends on individuals of the form.
To handle
Hegel’s priority of form, we need to highlight a different way of thinking
about dependence and priority. Again I am drawing on recent work on
Aristotle, some of it noting a connection to accounts of ontological
dependence in contemporary metaphysics, as in Kit Fine.
The point can be formulated in terms of dependence between
essences, but to match the above
I would say this:
Y
what-depends on X iff what it is to be Y depends on what it is to be X.
X is
what-prior to Y if and only if, Y what-depends on X, and not vice versa.
The priority claim in Hegel, above, is this: a substantial form is
what-prior to individuals of that form.
The idea
here is not an overall picture of
reciprocity or holism. The overall picture is not what-priority going one
way balanced against that-priority going the other way.
Maybe that picture would be coherent
if one thought of a relation superficially similar to what-priority, but
implicitly or explicitly specific
to relations between mental representations (one being such that it cannot
be understood except in terms of another), or judgments or sentences (one
being such that its meaning depends on other judgments in a space of reasons
in the sense of justifications)—thus allowing this relation to be innocent
of implications about worldly existences and any worldly dependencies. But
that would take as basic from the start, building on, a form of dualism—world
vs. mind, or
causality vs.
normativity (or vs. a supposedly
purely epistemic account of
explanation, etc.). Hegel would not work from dualism-dependent
conceptions, nor associate this with Aristotle. The key to escaping the
familiar deflationary path is that the what-priority Hegel sees in Aristotle
and adopts is metaphysical, and applies not only to the metaphysics of mind,
nature, and relations between them—it applies also to metaphysics prior to
any such distinctions. And this metaphysical what-priority is not compatible
with reverse that-priority.
Take our example: if a particular human
only is what it is given the form
of human being, then it is also the case that, if the form were not, then
this human being would not be. Thus: “The indispensable foundation, the
concept, the universal” (WL: 16–7/21:15). In general, if X is
what-prior to Y, then Y that-depends on X, ruling out that-priority of Y.
It follows
that, in the substantial form case, we now have no that-priority at all;
rather, the form human being, on the one hand, and particular human beings,
on the other, are reciprocally that-dependent. That is compatible with this
being overall a case of metaphysical priority of form, namely, its
what-priority.
As a
general pattern:
1.
X is
what-prior to Y.
2.
X and Y
are reciprocally that-dependent.
Here the reciprocity is subordinate to what is overall a case of
metaphysical priority, namely here the what-priority of form.
Although
not a case of what-priority, there is an otherwise matching case made
explicit in Aristotle. And this is very frequently cited in contemporary
metaphysics, with non-Hegelians treating it as comprehensible (e.g. Schaffer
2009: 375). The idea is this: “there being a man reciprocates as to
implication of existence with the true statement about it” (Categories:
14b). This reciprocal that-dependence is compatible with a metaphysical
priority on one side:
whereas
the true statement is in no way the cause of the actual thing’s existence,
the actual thing does seem in some way the cause of the statement’s being
true. (Categories: 14b)
But coming
back specifically to what-priority, Hegel sees this in Aristotle far beyond
the case of substantial forms in relation to individuals. The case Hegel
thinks most important is Aristotle’s “priority in substance” of actuality (energeia)
over potentiality (dynamis).
The key for Hegel is this: energeia
is
… prior in
substance; firstly, because the things that are posterior in becoming are
prior in form and in substance, e.g. man is prior to boy and human being to
seed… Secondly, because everything that comes to be moves towards a
principle, i.e. an end … (Metaphysics:
1050a)
Beere argues that this cannot be (in my terms) that-priority, but must be
what-priority:
There is
priority in being because the sprout and the acorn are directed towards
becoming and then being different
from the way they are—namely being full-fledged oak trees—whereas an oak
tree is not … For this reason, there is a non-reciprocal dependence among
their essences. What it is to be an oak tree sprout depends on what it is to
be an oak tree, but not vice versa.
(2008: 437)
And I do think that Hegel sees such what-priority of developed stages in
Aristotle, and adopts it. For example,
what is a seed? “[T]he seed which
is the plant, in itself, is this, to develop itself” (EL: §124Z).
Hegel calls this kind of case “development” (Entwicklung),
and thinks it so important that it plays a role distinguishing the third
part of the Logic (EL:
§161). But the case of energeia,
and the relations between what- and that-priority here, are more complex and
less familiar, both in Aristotle and Hegel’s interpretation; these require a
separate study. So here I mention only the what-priority Hegel sees in such
cases of development.
With
respect to the whole of the general pattern noted above, it is easier to see
another case of this in the position Hegel adopts and attributes to
Aristotle concerning whole organisms in relation to their parts or
“members”: The whole organism is metaphysically prior, because it is
what-prior. From this Hegel takes a that-dependence of part on whole to
follow: if the part’s being what
it is depends on the whole, then that
there is such a part also depends on there being the whole:
The
individual members of the body are what they are only by means of their
unity and in relation to it. Thus, for example, a hand that is severed from
the body, is a hand only in name, but not in reality, as Aristotle already
noted. (EL: §216Z)
Note: the idea is not that the hand would be the same, without the whole
body, and we would use a different word (actually, here, we would not); form
is part of the metaphysics, and without the whole body, there would be no
hand. This is compatible with the recognition of that-dependence the other
way as well: it cannot be the case that there is a whole organism unless it
is the case that there are its parts.
So we have another case in which we can understand the coherence of the
general pattern: reciprocity of that-dependence, subordinated to what is
overall the metaphysical priority of one side, namely, what-priority.
III. A model for Hegel’s absolute and resolutions to
the problems
We can now
frame a proposal, namely, that Hegel extends the general pattern, above,
throughout metaphysics, and all the way to his own version of a metaphysical
definition of the absolute or God. This will later require a slight
qualification. And it may be, more than Hegel admits, at odds with the
account of God in Aristotle’s
Metaphysics.
Still, it allows an initial model of Hegel’s absolute, giving reason to
think our initial problems to be solvable—so that we can then turn below to
fill in details of Hegel’s specifically idealist metaphysics, in which the
absolute is thought, itself prior
to being.
Consider
the two respects of comparability with God in other metaphysical systems,
with which I began, the first being
priority. Application of the general pattern above suggests that Hegel’s
absolute is supposed to be metaphysically prior in the same sense that he
himself sees a substantial form as prior: the absolute would be what-prior,
so that everything non-absolute will depend, for its being what it is, on
the absolute, and not vice versa.
The second
respect was self-determination.
This is where we need to extend
the model, beyond the case of any old substantial form, all the way to
something absolute. But the
natural extension is clear: if the absolute is specifically
what-prior to non-absolute, then
the corresponding sense of self-determination would be that the absolute
makes itself what it is. I will
put this by saying that the absolute is “what-self-determining”. So the
general pattern above is extended to a model of the absolute:
1.
The
absolute is what-self-determining
2.
The
absolute is what-prior to everything non-absolute
3.
The
absolute and the non-absolute are reciprocally that-dependent
A new
concern opens up here, to be sure, concerning (1): Analogies with organisms
and substantial forms are no longer as helpful here, insofar as they do not
seem to be examples of absolute what-self-determination. So the problem is:
how can we make the idea of what-self-determination comprehensible, and in a
way non-Hegelians might possibly understand? I try to answer in terms of
Hegel’s idealism in the Logic,
below.
But we do
not need more about self-determination to see why we should expect the
initial problems, from above, to be solvable. One facet of the first problem
concerned thoroughgoing mediation.
But our model allows the absolute to be mediated (in being
that-dependent); we have already seen that it is comprehensible—even to
non-Hegelians—to say that some X is mediated, in this sense, while claiming
that the overall metaphysical picture is that on which X is metaphysically
prior, namely, what-prior. So mediation is no bar to making sense of the
metaphysical priority of the absolute.
The other
facet concerned Hegel’s anti-dualism,
his denying, for example, a dualism between being and thought (e.g. WL:
49/21:45). But consider the what-priority of oak tree to sprout. The seed
grows gradually, without jumping any gulf. Here non-Hegelians—philosophers
working on Aristotle, for example, and drawing on contemporary
metaphysics—appear at least to understand the claim that X can be
metaphysically prior to Y, even while Y is not utterly distinct from X, but
indeed its essence depends on X.
The second
problem was that Hegel appeared doomed, when it comes to arguing for his
absolute, because such an argument would need the PSR, and yet Hegel seems
to contradict that in recognizing incomplete explicables (e.g. EL:
§248A), and in criticizing Spinoza and acosmism (WL: 61/5:85). But
the pattern above suggests this need not be a problem: Hegel can defend a
PSR (or, if you prefer, a PSR analogue) limited to
issues related to
what-dependence. And Hegel could argue
against a more general PSR, and in particular any PSR that would apply
to all issues, distinct from those above, concerning
that-dependence. He can argue
against principles like: Nothing is
brute. But defend something like:
Nothing is brutely what it is.
It should be easy to see at least an initial sense of why the latter is just
what is useful, relative to trying to prove that there must be something
absolute in the sense of being what-self-determining, and what-prior to
everything else.
The next
step is to connect this model with the details of Hegel’s specifically
idealist metaphysics, where the absolute is specifically a kind of
thought, prior to
being. One way to try this would
be to look at Hegel’s comparisons between his idealism and Aristotle on God,
pure actuality (energeia), and
thought thinking itself (EL: §236Z, §577). But this would require a
separate study, because these issues in Aristotle are difficult and less
familiar, and Hegel greatly complicates matters by interpreting Aristotle on
God in a less familiar and radical manner.
So here I set that path aside and turn to the broad outlines of the argument
for idealism in the Logic. There
is no space here to defend each step, consider interpretive options for each
step, or even mention each step in the
Logic. The point is rather to
highlight some of what specifically would follow from the application of the
model above, and only specifically to show that the way is clear to make
sense of Hegel’s idealism specifically as an account of the
self-determination and metaphysical priority of an absolute, and in a manner
that solves the problems above.
IV. Application to the outlines of the Logic
Prior to
the beginning of the Logic
proper, Hegel takes himself to have established the need for metaphysics, in
which pure thought will abstract from sense perception and intuition.
The structure will be this: First (in the doctrine of being) Hegel argues
for contradictions in any attempt at a metaphysics of immediacy. That is to
say, he argues that metaphysics must rather build around the resource of
some mediation or dependence relation between one thing and another (e.g.
grounding), or around the mediation of something by itself, or
self-determination. Then (in the doctrine of essence) Hegel argues for
contradictions in any attempt at a metaphysics built
just on a mediation or dependence
relation between one thing and another.
So (in the doctrine of the concept) Hegel draws the conclusion that
metaphysics must be built around self-determination, and builds just this.
Being: The
Logic begins with the argument
that metaphysics at the start has reason to prefer to all others one
specific metaphysical view, namely, Parmenides’s monism. The reason for this
preference is that the lack of assumptions, as from sense perception—for
example, that there are red
things—privileges the theory of what is as just
pure being, which immediately is
(EL: §86). But Hegel further argues, in the first application of the
dialectical method, that drawing the Parmenidean conclusion for these
reasons—even if the best first step—in fact reveals a contradiction,
providing otherwise inaccessible reason to revise this metaphysics. In
particular, we are trying to draw the conclusion that
what is is pure being, but the
form of this claim initially justified leaves being so indeterminate as to
supposedly be nothing at all (EL: §87). Overall the first few
resulting transitions are supposed to provide reason to conclude that the
object of metaphysics must include
determinacy, bringing us to “determinate being” (Dasein).
The
remaining question in “Being” is whether sense can be made of determinacy
within the constraints of the focus on immediacy. Hegel argues the negative:
Determinacy inevitably raises problems concerning mediation, and
(importantly for our purposes) specifically concerning what-dependence. For
example, we can try to preserve immediacy by thinking a ‘something” (Etwas)
as determinate insofar as immediately distinguished by a
quality. Then we are thinking
what is as perishable: ‘something
is what it is by virtue of its quality and when it loses its quality it
stops being what it is” (EL: §90Z). For this kind of ‘something”,
then, “finitude and
alterability belong to its being” (EL:
§92). But then it is what it is only in virtue of, and so in a way dependent
on, not yet having ceased to be, or not crossing the “limit” between it and
the “other” that would be if it were not:
‘something
is what it is only in its limit” and “this something is what it is through
it” (WL: 99–100/21:114–5). Hegel argues that a regress of
what-dependence of merely finite somethings would follow, ad infinitum
(EL: §93).
Application of the model above suggests that what is going here is that
Hegel is defending and beginning to apply the limited PSR from above,
according to which nothing is, in
brute terms, what it is:
He argues that metaphysics must include things that are determinately
what they are. The simplest
attempts to make sense of such determinacy require what-dependence. And if
we take something finite, in a sense requiring what-dependence on something
else—and even if we add an unending regress of finites—we still would
require something further on which to be what-dependent. So metaphysics will
ultimately have to include something “infinite” in the relevant sense. But
within the limits of the doctrine of being, Hegel argues that we give only
inadequate accounts of a “bad or
negative infinity”, thought only
as not finite, or
not dependent, bringing us back
to immediate being, with its supposed empty indeterminacy; we can here only
think that there “ought to be”
the infinite source of things being determinately what they are (EL:
§94).
Essence:
The next attempt is a metaphysics built from a mediation or determination
relation between two things; Hegel will argue that such a metaphysics cannot
succeed in its own terms—which is to say, without instead building on
self-determination.
Here is an
example of an argument I have stressed as paradigmatic of “essence” (Kreines
2004, 2015). At one point Hegel considers “ground” as a way of one thing
depending on or being determined by another. He takes as an example some
observed phenomena, like the movement of bodies, being such that it does not
determine, cause or explain itself—and having a “ground” in forces. But
restricted to doing without a metaphysics of self-determination, we meet a
dilemma. If forces are not distinct from the explanandum, then (within the
restriction) a force is just a non-explanatory re-description of the
explanandum (see the section on “formal ground”; WL: 397ff./11:302).
If forces are distinct, then (within this restriction) they would be yet
more things needing a ground in something else, if any grounding was
required in the first place (see the section on “real ground”; WL:
402ff/11:307). Either way, the reason we posited grounds is not satisfied:
“this method of explaining from grounds does not satisfy its own
expectations, that it itself demands something quite different from such
grounds” (WL: 402/6:102). What
is demanded—Hegel is arguing
throughout “essence”—is some form of metaphysical self-determination (i.e.
the “concept”), since this problem generalizes to forms of dependence of one
thing on another.
By the end
of “essence”, Hegel is completing a
reductio against any PSR that would encompass any sense of
that-dependence distinct from what-dependence. We might have wanted to
demand, just for any X that is,
there be some Y that is independently, and is the reason
that X is. Such a principle would
seem to require a reason why there is something rather than nothing. But the
principle would demand an absolute. One possibility would then be immediate
being as ultimate reason, the absolute “of the Eleatics”, or God as “the
real
in all reality, the
supremely real” (EL: §86). “Being” argues that this turns out too
indeterminate to make possible an answer to any determinate why question.
The alternative would be a causa sui:
just as a cause is responsible for the existence of its effect, this
would be something that causes its own existence, and the existence of
everything else as well. “Essence” argues that it is incoherent to take a
causal relation between things and try to build or derive a self-caused
absolute (EL: §153ff.). Either way, then, a PSR applying to
that-dependence forces incoherence.
Concept:
The doctrine of the concept turns toward self-determination (EL:
§163A). Hegel initially compares the way a substantial form of a plant would
explain the directed series of growing stages in the development of the
plant (EL: §§161–7Z). But the
Logic’s
concluding account is more self-reflective. Hegel finds in the “method”
of the Logic
the
demonstration that thought itself
is self-determining: The Logic
starts with just the concept, as
Hegel says, of pure thought of what
is. And just this alone is supposed to determine a specific beginning
point for thought, namely, Parmenides’s pure being. And just this first step
is supposed to force, in the dialectic, further revisions in metaphysics,
pushing toward “determinate being”, beyond to “essence” and “ground”, and to
idealism. In sum, just the concept of thought itself fills in a series of
determinate contents of thought—it generates a specific, directed ordering
or structure of thought. One concept—the concept of thought itself, rather
than the concept of human being, for example—is uniquely self-determining.
Hegel consequently calls this not any old concept, or
a concept, but
the concept. Hegel says of the
method of the Logic:
… what is
to be considered as method here is only the movement of the
concept itself … its movement is
the universal absolute activity,
the self-determining and self-realizing movement. (WL:
737/12:238).
For us it is crucial that the sense of self-determination is specifically
what-self-determination. So when
talking about the structure of the
Logic at its start, Hegel says that this structure is yet to be
demonstrated, or derived from thought itself, saying that “in philosophy,
demonstrating [beweisen] is
equivalent to showing how the object makes itself-through and out of
itself—into what it is” (EL: §83Z).
Opponents
will have ideas about what to challenge here: They can argue against the
case that there is a uniquely privileged starting point for such pure
thought, and/or they can challenge later arguments that difficulties
internal to one form of thought require a transition to the next. But that
the points at which to challenge are clear suggests that the
meaning of the claim that thought
is self-determining is not entirely lost in Hegel-esque formulations that
seem at odds with themselves to any opponent; the meaning is clear enough to
see how to object.
One might
also worry that self-determining thought, in the above sense, cannot be an
absolute that is metaphysically prior to the non-absolute. The issue here is
whether we can explain the meaning of such a priority claim. Applying the
model above, the point will be that the self-determination of thought or
“the concept” is responsible for everything else being
what it is. In other words: “…
the concept is what is truly first and the things are what they are, thanks
to the activity of the concept dwelling in them and revealing itself in
them” (EL: §163Z). Hegel
sometimes puts the point—as where he is discussing the “method” of the
Logic as ‘self-determining and
self-realizing movement”—by saying that “the
concept is all” (WL:
737/12:238). And that might seem to suggest that everything real is
absolutely self-determining; in other words: there would be only the
absolute. But this would leave too little distance between Hegel and the “acosmism”
he complains about when discussing Spinoza. Hegel’s point allows that there
are some things that are non-absolute or finite. It is just that, to
be finite is to be an incomplete
form of the infinite—of the self-determination of thought. Or, in more
detail, what it is to be a finite thing is to partially possess within
itself a concept that determines itself, and yet to fail in some way and to
some degree to have this “completely”:
Finite
things are finite because, and to the extent that, they do not possess the
reality of their concept completely within them but are in need of other
things for it. (WL: 672/6:465)
This
what-priority of thought will also play a large role outside the
Logic, in the
Realphilosophie. Here the topics
are things aside from the thought that is, strictly speaking, the object of
the Logic. All of them are
supposed to depend, for their being what they are, on the self-determination
of pure thought. Among the natural phenomena,
life is supposed to be closest to
the complete self-determination of thought. But take even lifeless matter:
what it is is supposed to be such as to require understanding in
terms of a system rotating around a centre of gravity, which is itself a
specific way of being partially but incompletely self-determining. In the
Philosophy of Spirit, something
similar applies to minds; the short story is that to be a mind is to be, to
a degree greater than anything natural, self-determining.
It is now time for the
qualifications I mentioned, along the way, concerning the approach to Hegel
via Aristotelian priority. First, my interpretation of Aristotle on
substantial forms might have seemed to suggest that Hegel holds that, where
an individual human is what she is in virtue of the substantial form of
human being, this form is something ultimate in the sense that the
what-dependence comes to an end here. We can now see that this is not
Hegel’s view; his idealism holds that all what-dependence terminates with
the self-determination of absolute thought. Further, my beginning with
what-priority might have seemed to suggest building a metaphysics from a
basic resource of a dependence relation between distinct things. But
“essence” argues that this cannot succeed; the importance of what-priority,
for us, was that this leads us to what-self-determination, which
retrospectively turns out to be the real resource from which Hegel’s
metaphysics is built. There are
dependence relations, but they are such that one cannot understand them
without thinking of that which is depended upon as (to some degree)
self-determining.
In any
case, we can now finish applying the model, from above. Since absolute
thought is what-prior to everything else, nothing else can be unless there
is this self-determining structure of thought—all is also that-dependent on
thought. But the model includes
reciprocal that-dependence. So the idea is that the object of the
Logic—the self-determination of
pure thought—is also that-dependent on its realizations covered in the
Realphilosophie. This is part of
what Hegel means, for example, in characterizing the
Logic as concerned with a “realm
of shadows”, which cannot be without some kind of ‘sensuous concretion” (WL:
37/5:55).
Note
something unusual about the resulting metaphysical idealism. In particular,
there is nothing here like the claim that everything real must be “in” any
mind or minds. Those forms of idealism claim a that-priority of mind or
minds: a Berkeleyan idea, for example, cannot exist unless there is a mind
that it is “in”, and the reverse does not hold. But this is no part of
Hegel, whose claim is that the absolute—thought—is what-prior to the
non-absolute, but reciprocally that-dependent. So neither thought nor
anything else exists independently of nature, and should be held responsible
for the fact that nature exists.
It is in this sense that we can understand why Hegel thinks that the right
sort of metaphysical idealism will also be realist (WL: 124/21:143).
Granted,
all this raises many further questions. But it has not been my aim to answer
all questions. What I have tried to do is to work my way far enough to
demonstrate solutions to the specific problems raised above. These might
initially have appeared to
clearly block the way to philosophical explanation of a metaphysical
absolute in Hegel, with the two senses of comparability. But they do not.
We have
the priority of Hegel’s absolute:
the absolute, or thought, is metaphysically prior in just the sense that
Hegel thinks Aristotle holds substantial form to be prior: thought is
what-prior to everything else.
And we are not left, in interpreting Hegel on
self-determination, with just
saying that Hegel accepts and rejects the same claim, in some way that
non-Hegelians would not understand how there could be a coherent
philosophical view at all. Hegel’s claim is just that thought makes itself
what it is. For Hegel argues that
the endeavour of pure thought privileges a first theory of what
is—Parmenides’s—and this and each further step uncovers contradictions that
force thought farther through a series of determinate theories, in the
direction of Hegel’s conclusions. Thought is supposed to give itself this
directed structure.
Furthermore, Hegel’s commitment to
thoroughgoing mediation is neither reason to try to deny that he
endorses this kind of metaphysical absolute, nor to conclude that we can
only express his view by saying that he both endorses this and denies such
an absolute. For this is simply compatible, just in the manner that Hegel
also clearly sees an Aristotelian metaphysical priority of substantial form
as compatible with the dependence of form; for Hegel, absolute thought is
reciprocally that-dependent with its non-absolute realizations.
Nor is
Hegel’s anti-dualism reason to
deny that he endorses the metaphysical priority of an absolute. We have
compared the metaphysical priority of developed oak over sprout. Hegel’s
claim is that there is a gradual scale of realizations of absolute thought,
without any break or discontinuity. All realizations of absolute thought are
approximations, and what they are
is fixed by a degree and a manner of approximation. They all
are absolute thought, even where
everything non-absolute also falls short, leaving enough distance for the
priority claim.
Note how
these points combine: The absolute is dependent, in being that-dependent. Is
that not some mitigation of its absoluteness? No, insofar as what it depends
on are forms of itself. Compare Hegel’s formulation concerning the
dependence of the absolute or (here) the “infinite”: “[t]he sole question is
… how to combine that the infinite starts precisely from an other and yet in
doing so starts only from itself” (DG 157/17:435).
Finally,
with respect to the second problem, we cannot rule out, in advance of closer
engagement with the details, prospects for Hegel’s defence of his
metaphysical idealism by argument: he is not in the position of needing and
yet contradicting one and the same PSR. What Hegel defends is a restricted
version of the PSR. Not: nothing is
brute. But rather: nothing is, in
brute terms, what it is. This is just what is needed by someone
arguing that there must be an absolute that (i) makes itself what it is, and
(ii) is what-prior to everything else. Hegel argues against any PSR that
would encompass distinct issues concerning that-dependence, or suggest the
need (in this sense) of an explanation of why there is something, rather
than nothing. In other words, Hegel is free to try to argue that this last
demand is mistaken or illegitimate. To recognize him as doing so is not to
give a deflationary reading of his philosophy—to read it as either
non-metaphysical, or else as a purely holist metaphysics. The way is free to
try to argue, using the limited PSR he defends, for the self-determination
and metaphysical priority of absolute thought.
Abbreviations
EL
= Hegel, Encyclopaedia Logic,
trans. T. F. Geraets, H. S. Harris, and W. A. Suchting (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1991).
WL =
Hegel,
Science of Logic,
trans.
A. V. Miller (London: Allen & Unwin, 1969).
VGP
= Lectures on the History of
Philosophy, trans. E. S. Haldane and F. H. Simson (Lincoln: University
of Nebraska Press, 1995).
DG = Lectures on the Proofs for the Existence of God,
trans. P. C. Hodgson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007)
References to Hegel’s original German are by (volume:
page in
that edition) and are to:
Gesammelte Werke
(Hamburg: Meiner, 1968), and:
Werke in zwanzig Bände,
eds. E. Moldenhauer and K. Michel (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp,
1970–1).
E
= Spinoza, “Ethics”, trans.
E. Curley in E. Curley (ed.), A Spinoza Reader, (Princeton: Princeton
University Press,
1994). Cited by part (I–V), proposition (P), definition (D),
scholium (S) and corollary (C).
SSW
= Schelling,
Sämmtliche Werke,
ed.
K. F. A.
Schelling (Stuttgart: Cotta, [1856-1861]).
Bibliography
Aristotle. (1984), The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford
Translation. Edited by J. Barnes. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Beere, J. (2008), “The Priority in Being of Energeia” in Crubellier, Jaulin,
Lefebvre and Morel (eds.), Dynamis: Autour de la puissance chez Aristote.
Louvain: Peeters.
Beiser, F. C. (2005), Hegel. New York: Routledge.
Brandom, R. (2001), “Holism and Idealism in Hegel’s Phenomenology”,
Hegel-Studien 36: 57–92.
Cohen, S. M. (2008), ‘substances” in G. Anagnostopoulos (ed.), The
Blackwell Companion to Aristotle.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Düsing, K. (1986), “Hegel und die Geschichte der Philosophie”,
Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 48 (1): 135–6.
Ferrarin, A. (2001),
Hegel and Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
García, M. (2016), “Energeia vs Entelecheia”, Tópicos, Revista de
Filosofía 51: 113–37.
Horstmann, R. P. (2006), “Hegels Ordnung der Dinge”, Hegel-Studien
41: 9–50.
Inwood, M. (1983), Hegel. London: Routledge.
Kern, W. (1971), “Die Aristotelesdeutung Hegels”, Philosophisches
Jahrbuch 78: 237–59.
Knappik, F. (2016), “Hegel’s Essentialism: Natural Kinds and the Metaphysics
of Explanation in Hegel’s Theory of “the Concept”“, European Journal of
Philosophy 24 (4): 760–87.
Kreines, J. (2004),
“Hegel’s Critique of Pure Mechanism and the Philosophical Appeal of the
Logic Project”, European Journal of Philosophy 12 (1): 38–74.
Kreines, J. (2015), Reason in the World: Hegel’s Metaphysics and its
Philosophical Appeal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Malink, M. (2013), “Essence and Being”, Oxford Studies in Ancient
Philosophy 45: 341–62.
McTaggart, J. (1901). Studies in
Hegelian Cosmology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Peramatzis, M. (2011), Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Pinkard, T. (1988), Hegel’s Dialectic: The Explanation of Possibility.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Pippin, R. (2018), Hegel’s Realm of Shadows: Logic as Metaphysics in
The Science of Logic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Schaffer, J. (2009), “On What Grounds What” in D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and
R. Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Spinoza, B. 1985: The Collected Works
of Spinoza. (edited and translated by E. Curley). Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Stern, R. (1990), Hegel, Kant and the Structure of the Object. London:
Routledge.
Stern, R. (2009), Hegelian Metaphysics.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Theunissen, M. (1980), Sein und Schein. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Thanks, for comments and discussion, to Mark Alznauer, Brady Bowman,
Marcela García, Jake McNulty, Dean Moyar, and Johannes-Georg
Schülein. And thanks to audiences at the Freie Universität Berlin,
Humboldt Universität zu Berlin, Northwestern University, and the
University of Chicago.
My
topic encompasses both versions, which differ in other respects but
not, in my view, on points discussed here.
References to Aristotle are cited from The Complete Works of
Aristotle (1984).
I
have here on some points moved farther in this inflationary
metaphysical direction than I had in my (2015).
I
will come to passages on Hegelian priority below. Note that we
cannot read Hegel as eliminating everything but an absolute, leaving
no priority over anything; he criticizes this view, calling it “acosmism”
in discussions of Spinoza (discussed below). It is true that Hegel’s
metaphysics is not built on the resource of priority; see the
following paragraph.
Attempts to build metaphysics on the priority of one thing over
another fail in “essence”; ultimately metaphysics must be built not
from that but from, in the final part of the
Logic, an account of
self-determination or “das Wirkende
seiner selbst” (EL:
§163A).
He reads Hegel as
replacing the concerns of
metaphysica specialis,
preferring “non-extravagant” metaphysics or ontology, which is
supposed to elude Kant’s critique of metaphysics, rather than
exceeding its limits and arguing for such a challenge to it (2009,
ch. 1). Pippin (2018) is about much else as well, but shares these
deflationary points: “the intelligibility conditions of ordinary
objects” as Aristotle’s topic, compatible with Kant’s critique
(2018: 94), and Hegel’s “model” in which something else “takes the
place” of questions of special metaphysics, including about God
(2018: 124).
Addressing that different
question would require dealing with the vast literature on it; for
orientation, see Kern (1971), Düsing (1986: 97ff.), and Ferrarin
(2001).
E.g. “…subjective and objective, or also of thought and being, of
concept and reality… are now in their truth, that is, in their
unity…” (WL: 49/21:45).
This is at least part of the point in the criticism of the
philosophies of immediacy at §§61–78.
See Stern’s own view (2009: 30–4), and similarly McTaggart’s
(1901:256).
See Spinoza 1985, 244 and 246 for Spinoza’s “A7” and “A11” in
context of his exposition of Descartes. On Spinoza’s argument for
his God as employing the PSR throughout, see especially Garrett
(1979).
Spinoza does not use it; Hegel does use Leibniz’s terminology, but
for something he thinks more specific to Leibniz, e.g. EL:
§121Z.
E.g. EL: §248R. And on this see my (2015).
Beiser 2005, 170–1. Cf. Horstmann 2006: 27–8. Note that Beiser sees
the resulting problem here, treating it as about necessity, and
powerfully arguing that familiar attempts to solve it fail (2006:
76–9).
Comparable tensions often show up in interpretations of the relation
between “essence” and “the concept” in the
Logic, e.g. Theunissen
sees the former as more critical and the latter as ‘schizophrenic”
in relation to special metaphysics (1980: 61); cf. Longuenesse
(2007: xviii).
The issues are complex, especially given Metaphysics Z.13,
but Hegel’s position is not unusual; see Cohen on those holding
“there is only one substantial form for all the particulars
belonging to the same species” (2008: 208).
E.g. “forms of perceptible objects … cannot exist without being
enmattered, hence not without some hylomorphic compound existing” (Malink
2013: 354). And others note the combination view in Hegel, including
again Stern (1990, 2009).
In
Schelling (SSW: II:3:60/130); on this in Schelling see García
2016.
Here again I am influenced by Beere, in a passage cited below (2009:
437), also by Peramatzis’s contrast between his “PIE” vs. “PIB”
(2011).
I
would resist putting the point in terms from Beiser, as an “ancient
Aristotelian distinction between what is first in order of
explanation and what is first in order of being” (2005: 56).
Here there is a contrast with Brandom’s similar seeming notion:
“Sense dependence does not entail reference dependence” (2001: 79).
I note another contrast concerning idealism at the end of this
article.
Hegel on the centrality of this: VGP: 19:154/3:138.
There are some issues about whether the dependence holds merely of
parts of certain kinds, rather than tokens; but I do not think this
makes a difference here.
See the following footnote.
Düsing (1986: 124ff.) argues that this is misinterpretation; for
further consideration see also Ferrarin (2001), and García (2016).
See e.g. EL: §38A. I defend Hegel’s position that those who
think to reject and avoid this kind of metaphysics in fact draw on
presuppositions about it in (2015).
See Pinkard (1988: 55ff.) on “essence” as about explanatory
relations.
I
think there is a compatible more general account of “essence” in
Knappik (2016: 8).
I
give an account of this scale from lesser to greater completeness in
(2015).
|