The Metaphysics of Reason and Hegel’s
Logic
A Conversation About James Kreines’ Reason in the World:
Hegel’s Metaphysics and its Philosophical Appeal
The following is a draft of Kreines'
portion of the conversation. The full and final version is
published in
Hegel-Studien
band 50 and includes contributions from:
Brady Bowman, Pennsylvania State University
Terry Pinkard, Georgetown University
Clinton Tolley, UCSD
Introduction to
Reason in the World
By James Kreines
I would like to begin our conversation with
a brief word about my book,
Reason in the World:
Hegel’s Metaphysics and its Philosophical Appeal. Generally,
my work aims to read figures in the history of philosophy in
light of their arguments. In my book I take my orientation from
something else in addition, namely, the sense in which Hegel
aims to construct not a heap of arguments but a
system. This
systematicity is, of course, often discussed, and in many ways.
But I think that such a system specifically requires something
surprising: a metaphilosophical commitment concerning a kind of
problem or issue as fundamental to philosophy. A system would
carry such a commitment through completely or absolutely. I
focus more specifically on Hegel’s
Logic, but this
itself argues about a great many issues. The questions are: what
is the specifically metaphilosophical commitment that is
supposed to be responsible for
organizing or
unifying all the
diversity into parts of a system? And, what supposedly
fundamental problems are supposed to be finally resolved at the
end of the Logic?
Lack of consideration of metaphilosophy can
lead to hasty judgments. For example, some might criticize
systematic philosophy because they think it must fundamentally
aspire to a foundational certainty and with it to pass judgment
on all other disciplines or knowledge claims. But even if they
are right about that
project being hopeless, if they just assume that this is what
systematic philosophy must be, without considering alternatives,
then this is no reason to conclude that systematic philosophy
must be hopeless. And such an assumption would be a bad position
from which to start with Hegel.
What sort of metaphilosophy would provide a
more promising approach to Hegel? Here is an illustrative
example of a contender I think important, although it is not my
own view: Perhaps Hegel takes as fundamental some broadly
epistemological issues raised in Kant’s Transcendental Analytic
of the Critique of Pure
Reason. So the fundamental issue would concern something
like the possibility of a relation between our cognition and its
objects, and the project would address this via deductions
concerning the conceptual conditions of the possibility of this
relation.
Many different sub-varieties of this approach to Hegel have
flourished, focusing specifically on the possibility of
knowledge, or else of intentionality, or else of normative
concept use, etc.
Some of my worries about this general
approach are internal, and concern carrying through
systematically. For example, proponents of the proposal might
begin by saying that Hegel argues against a competing
theory—against, it is often said, some version of “realism”—on
grounds that this cannot give a satisfactory resolution of a
supposedly fundamental problem, in that it cannot give a
satisfying a meta-level theory about how cognition relates to
objects in any object-level claim, thought, or theory. But a
system constructed like this would eventually have to provide
the satisfying meta-level theory resolving that issue. It cannot
go on to say much later that Hegel rather dissolves the problem
by rejecting the dualism between object-level and meta-level,
focusing then on something else—such as a theory of unending and
ongoing social contestation. For then there never was grounds to
reject the competitors earlier, as there would be no measure by
which they fail and this version of Hegel succeeds. Even if much
of this story is still making progress with individual elements
in Hegel, the initial promise of answering the crucial question
would then have been dashed, and the question re-arises: what is
the fundamental issue, systematically pursued and ultimately
resolved, that unifies the elements into parts of Hegel’s
system?
A common external complaint about that
Transcendental-Analytic approach to Hegel argues as follows:
Yes, extending the
strategy of the Transcendental Analytic is part of what
Hegel is doing, but this omits the fact that Hegel also
pursues of more metaphysical issues, like those raised by
Spinoza. I am sympathetic with this orientation, but I find
the specific complaint insufficient. For one thing, the
Transcendental-Analytic approach can recognize a metaphysics in
Hegel; it need only argue that Hegel understands or transforms
metaphysics in light of the broadly epistemological issues,
about the relation of cognition to objects, that he is supposed
to take as fundamental.[2] For
another thing, the complaint as it stands gives up on
systematicity, settling for a heap of issues: these and
also those;
transcendental deductions and
also Spinozism; etc.
And so there is a danger that all sides can let their implicit
metaphilosophical commitments drift or pile up into a heap.
My aim, then, is to make explicit the way
in which the question of system is metaphilosophical, and then
to rethink Hegel anew
in that light, focusing specifically on the
Logic and most of all
on its concluding sections. If the new account of Hegel’s
organizing orientation is correct, then I should be able to
borrow the best insights and benefits from other approaches,
even if they normally compete with one another, by placing
everything in a new context that fits it all together
systematically. I include from the start the aim of not diluting
Hegel’s ambitiousness in order to curry favor in the
contemporary climate. I begin by holding that Hegel takes as
basic some metaphysical issues—drawn in particular from Kant’s
Transcendental Dialectic. Hegel then radically and
systematically transforms everything else, including
epistemology, in light of those metaphysical issues. We can say
that the basic issues concern grounds or conditions, and
ultimately the completeness of grounding or “the
unconditioned”—as long as we consistently think of these in
metaphysical terms, avoiding a drift into thinking of
epistemological issues, for example, about whether and how our
knowledge might be conditioned. Now Kant argues that, although
there are such metaphysical issues of basic interest to our
reason itself, our attempts at theoretical philosophy in
response generate contradictions, preventing us from answering
questions that are metaphysical in that particular sense.
But Hegel seeks to show that the contradictions of the Dialectic
teach a different lesson, about how to fix metaphysics in that
same sense involving the objects of reason. So Hegel’s project
in the Logic is
neither like Kant’s positive project of the deductions from the
Transcendental Analytic, nor like Spinoza’s pre-Kantian
metaphysics; Hegel’s project is more distinctive: it is to
reconstruct a metaphysics-centered philosophy on grounds of what
he takes (rightly, in my view) to be the strongest criticism of
metaphysics, from the contradictions of the Dialectic.
The
aim of all this is not to claim a somehow definitive weighing of
costs and benefits in Hegel’s favor over Kant. Nor is it to
defend both by assimilating them. Rather, it is to find one
approach that brings into view strong arguments on conflicting
sides of a deep divide.
My discussion partners have done a
wonderful job of raising questions that bring out crucial
junctures in the argument of the book from this point. So I turn
the floor over to them.
Systematicity and the Defense of Reason in the World
Jim
Kreines – Claremont McKenna
1.
I am extremely grateful to Brady Bowman, Terry
Pinkard, and Clinton Tolley for their thoughtful comments and
generous attention to my book. I have learned much from each of
them, in this exchange and others, and I am happy to have this
opportunity to thank them. What I would like to do in this paper is
to advance the conversation further, in defense of my position in
Reason in the World.
Regrettably, space constraints prevent me from adequately addressing
all of their comments and questions; but all of them have been a
helpful spur for future work, for which I am thankful as well.
I begin
with challenges pressed by Clinton Tolley concerning my account of
Hegel’s interpretation and criticism of Kant. My core argument is
that Hegel fundamentally aims to turn Kant’s Antinomy against Kant
and Kant’s claim about our having an epistemic limit to the bounds
of sensibility. Kant thinks that antinomy conflict arise because of
the application of a conception of the unconditioned—adequate, in
itself—to a domain that it cannot fit, namely, the spatio-temporal.
Hegel, as Tolley cites me, responds that ‘the problem is rather
entirely internal to the
conception of the unconditioned that is so applied’ (168). More
specifically, I point to an internal tension in the conception,
arising from taking “the
perspective of the understanding”—a kind of substratum
thinking—“on the objects of reason” (EL §27).
Tolley questions many claims I make and need to
this end, but also questions some claims that I do not make, and I
think we differ over whether my argument requires these further
claims. The best way to respond is to take up the challenge to
clarify the argument in a manner making clear what is and is not
required.
First, begin with what I call the “paradigm
case”—not of Kant’s own views, but of what he calls “the metaphysics
of the understanding”, This is the case of the bare substratum. The
bare substratum is supposed to “support”, as it is often said, for
properties an object has. Arguing for existence would require
something like this paradigm
argument: If property P is had, then there must be something
that has it. If the answer characterizes that something only in
terms of a further property, Q, then the argument must bundle
all of the properties of
an object into a conjunctive property, and insist that there must be
something independent to correspond to the subject-pace in a
judgment attributing that conjunctive property. This would have to
be something independent of all the object’s properties: the bare
substrate.
Second, we then get a
paradigm problem: the
bare substrate thus demonstrated would be too bare to really support
anything. It is not itself a
supporting thing, because it would also have to be independent
of the property of being a
support. It would be, as Hegel says, “indifferent.”
In the paradigm case, we get a contradiction if we assert that
something serves the role of finally corresponding to the subject of
judgment and the role of
an explanatory support or ground. Now that is just a paradigm case
chosen to heighten and reveal the tension; Hegel thinks that
versions of this problem arise in subtler cases throughout
pre-Kantian metaphysics.
But the key in the book is the case of Kant and
specifically the Antinomy. I do not claim that Kant asserts that
there exist any bare substrata (161). For one thing, the issue here
is not about Kant’s existence claim, but rather his claims about the
guiding ideas of reason and the unconditioned. For another, the
ideas are cleverly not ideas of absolutely bare substrata. The issue
is whether subtler forms of substratum thinking shape the arguments
of the Antinomy and the conception of the unconditioned at work
there.
We can pursue this by asking, first, do we find
something of the form of
the paradigm argument?
And the answer is that we do. Take the thesis of the second
antinomy: A whole cannot consist of composition all the way down.
For we can bundle
composition relations—all
of them—and demand something further and independent to be the
something that stands in those relations, or does the composing.
Thus there must be simple parts. I think it is nice, but not
necessary, that Kant brings out the parallel by saying that the
thesis demands “subjects”, in the sense of “subjects of all
composition” (A436/B464), as if the proof might be expressed also by
demanding some parts to correspond to the subject-place in a
judgment about the bundled totality of composition. (I deny and have
no need of a view Tolley criticizes here, namely, that all ideas of
reason are supposed to be “absolutely
unconditioned, i.e., unconditioned in every respect” (xx). What
I say is that for a “given explanatory regress” what is required is
“relative to that
regress”—an
unconditioned “explainer for that regress” (186); e.g. for the
regress of composition, simplicity.)
Second, do we find something of the form of the
paradigm problem? Yes.
Just consider the supposedly simple parts. If they are spatially
extended, as would be required in a mathematical antinomy
considering a regress entirely within space and time, then we have
the antithesis to the second antinomy: those parts would have to be
composite as well as simple (A435/B463). So the only room for simple
parts would be something more like the objects considered in the
third and fourth, or dynamical, antinomies: something “different in
kind … outside the series” (A530/B558). But this opens an
explanatory gap. With the necessary being of the fourth Antinomy,
for example, if really necessary, then this would have to be outside
of the series of contingent causes in time. Note: this does not
require an absolutely bare substratum; as Tolley cites me, it “need
not be absolutely bare but would have to be at least bare relative
to that regress” (156). In this case, then, it would be bare
of temporal features, and
so unable to explain the temporal features of a cause in time (119;
A455/B483). Returning to the issues about a regress of composition
in space, a ground from outside this regress would not have to be
absolutely bare, but bare relative to that regress, or
non-extended—like a monad. Then the explanatory gap emerges because
compounding non-extended monads cannot itself explain spatial
extension. This is familiar from puzzles about some of Leibniz’s
formulations. Monads seem
indifferent, as Hegel puts it, to something they would be
supposed to ground.
And so Hegel holds, contra Kant, that the
conflict in an antinomy can be caused by a way in which a demand for
something like a substratum (the perspective of the understanding,
in the sense fixed by that bundling form of argument for something
underlying) conflicts with a demand for explanation or opposition to
explanatory gaps (the objects of
reason). Further, I think
this tension has nothing specifically to do with spatio-temporality.
So if Hegel is right, then the root of the conflict can rather be
the way in which Kant’s conception of the unconditioned, powering
both thesis and antithesis arguments, contains the above tension
between reason and the understanding. If so, then antinomy conflicts
can arise—as Hegel claims—in other cases apart from just a
specifically cosmological regress from the spatio-temporal (EL
§48R); I come to an example from Hegel below. And, if so, then this
is reason to take seriously Hegel’s proposal that antinomy conflicts
cannot be resolved by, and so do not require conclusions about,
spatio-temporality, including Kant’s epistemic limitation of our
cognition within the bounds of sensibility.
Tolley notes Kant’s own discussions of the
generation of the ideas; but Hegel’s case does not require an
unlikely admission by Kant there that he
means to mix in some
substratum-thinking so as to make the ideas internally conflicted.
What is important is how Kant actually argues in cases like those
noted above. Tolley also asks about the Paralogisms on the soul
and the Transcendental Ideal on God. But I argue that it is the
Antinomy that defends Kant’s epistemic limit,
so I set these other sections aside because they are not required
for the core topic.
Finally, Tolley makes a wonderful connection,
providing what seems to me a great way to adjudicate matters between
us: he says that my “treatment comes close to assuming that Kant
could (or should) have embraced what Karl Ameriks has characterized
as a ‘short argument’ for epistemic humility” (xx). I can see why
one might expect Hegel to have a problem here, given common
expectations. But this is part of why I mean to depart radically
from expected interpretations, and where I see my departure paying
large dividends. If we
read Hegel’s project as fundamentally an attempt to extract and
radicalize Kant’s deductions from the Transcendental Analytic,
then we seem doomed to
portray Hegel as uncharitably misunderstanding Kant, as if Kant
meant transcendental idealism in general or epistemic humility in
particular to rest on a “short argument”—one that bypasses the
details concerning the forms of our sensible intuition, space and
time, specifically found in the Aesthetic and the Dialectic. In the
book I agree with Ameriks
here and at many points: there is no sense engaging with Kant’s
epistemic limit in a way that fails to recognize that “it is the
Dialectic which nails down the strong claim that our (objective
theoretical) knowledge is absolutely limited”.
This is part of the reason why, against interpretations of Hegel on
the table, I side with Ameriks’ defense of Kant.
But this is also why I advocate rethinking Hegel anew, resting
everything now on this priority of the Dialectic. We can then see
how Hegel recognizes that Kant is aiming for something far better
than a short argument, specifically given the key role of the
Dialectic. But we can also see how precisely the strengths of Kant’s
case also open it to Hegel’s unusual response. In particular, a
short argument is hopeless: from the fact that our knowledge is
mediated, I argue that
it does not follow that our knowledge is
limited or
restricted (section 2.2).
But for precisely this reason, if Hegel has a case that the Antinomy
argument for epistemic limits fails to connect to spatio-temporality
in the manner Kant wants and needs, then Hegel has a case that the
attempt to use the Antinomy to support epistemic limits is weak—a
case that the Antinomy arguments can actually be used against Kant
himself in this respect.
I will return below to briefly respond to
Tolley concerning the absolute idea.
2.
Terry Pinkard focuses largely on the crucial
issue of the dialectical method in the
Logic, and draws out the
basics of my approach in this way:
What
holds all these arguments together is the dialectic… each such
attempt at a complete explanation results in some kind of
contradiction that propels us to move on to another type of
explanation…
However, I have
said that I do not want to compromise on Hegel’s ambitiousness, and
Pinkard worries that my approach forces compromise: “We do not have
a propulsion”; rather at each dialectical transition can only say
“let’s try something else”. I certainly agree that Hegel is more
ambitious than that. So
what differentiates my approach?
Again, I hold that everything traces back to
the issues from Kant’s Dialectic. So the first thing to say is that
Hegel draws a claim from Kant: reason is needed to guide all
theoretical inquiry, by means of its interest in the unconditioned,
or completeness of (in Hegel’s terms) reason in the world. As Kant’s
says, one cannot be guided by reason “unless one assumes (annimmt)”
(A307/B364) that there is something unconditioned. Hegel applies the
point to philosophy.
So philosophy too must begin with an assumption that this aim or
interest is not pointless, empty, meaningless or confused. Call this
claim dialectic-propulsion,
as it will provide the force and directionality.
To see how this works, consider Pinkard’s
example: Hegel thinks that lawful reality is so universally
dependent that this amounts to a kind of contradiction within it.
Pinkard is already worried:
…it
sounds as if the contradiction is between metaphysics and science,
not in the lawful itself. Physicists, to the extent that they are
indifferent to metaphysics, need not see any contradiction…
On my account,
there are two sides to this: the sense in which Hegel famously
leaves a real contradiction in the world here, and the sense in
which contradiction propels the
Logic forward.
To see the first sense of contradiction,
imagine that our physics recognizes three basic, lawfully
interacting kinds, X, Y, Z. But what
is X? What fixes its
identity?
At first, there need be no issue if one says that X is just the kind
defined by attraction to Y. But if the fixing of identity is thereby
deferred to Y, then an issue arises if the same is true of Y and so
on to all physical reality. Some will say that this is logically
impossible, sometimes saying that there cannot be relations without
relata. Russell finds the impossibility
obvious:
There
are many possible ways of turning some things hitherto regarded as
“real” into mere laws concerning the other things. Obviously there
must be a limit to this process, or else all the things in the world
will merely be each other’s washing. (1927, 325)
Some philosophers
continue to see here reason that there would have to be some more
independent character to physical reality, even if natural science
could never attain knowledge of it. But the pull in that direction
is that of what Hegel calls “the metaphysics of the understanding”:
the seeming need for something underlying the relational properties
here, so that we could bundle all of the relational properties, and
say in independent terms what they are properties of. Hegel thinks
that physicists tend to give in to the temptation, resulting in
their moving beyond physics and into philosophy and metaphysics—but
in unfortunate ways. For example, after the successful discovery of
gravitation, a philosophical mistake follows: “a physical meaning of
independent forces is
given” (EN §270A), as if thinking of forces as physical could
satisfy the apparent need for independently fixed identities.Hegel’s
position is that physicists should be
more indifferent to such
considerations; philosophers, meanwhile, should recognize that there
is a kind of Antinomy contradiction here (again one without special
tie to station-temporality), to which Russell is reacting, but it is
one that rather expresses the correct metaphysics of merely lawful
reality.
With respect, second, to propulsion, the key is
that lawful reality now looks explanatorily incomplete.
But, Kant and Hegel agree, theoretical inquiry is always guided
by the aim of the unconditioned, or completeness of explanation, and
can never be indifferent to this. Thus Kant says, as if he were
talking of Pinkard’s imagined physicists:
So-called indifferentists,
to the extent that they think anything at all, always
unavoidably fall back into metaphysical assertions, which they yet
professed so much to despise. (Ax)
In the book, I
dwell on the defense of Kant on this crucial point (Ch. 4). If
anyone holds that Hegel takes a deflationary or indifferentist tack
here, dismissing the centrality of the notion of explanatory
completeness drawn from Kant, then this reading would seem to me to
inevitably fail capture Hegel’s own conception of dialectic, and
specifically its ambitiousness. In any case, to apply the point to
examples like that of Pinkard’s physicists, I use the famous joke
from Molière:
I am
asked by the learned doctor for the cause and reason that opium
makes one sleep. To this I reply that there is a dormitive virtue in
it, whose nature it is to make the senses drowsy.
The idea is that
physicists pursue a kind of inquiry based in part on a commitment to
reject such dormitive-virtue explanations, and instead to seek more
complete explanations. But then they are contradicting their
commitment if they say what Pinkard imagines, namely, that physical
reality is exhausted by these three forces that we have found, while
professing indifference to explanations beyond the fact that x’s do
what they do on account of this being the nature of kind X, and so
on for kinds Y and Z.
So this is the source of the propulsion:
theoretical inquiry cannot rationally be content with this result so
far. Physicists will be propelled to doubt that they have found
everything, and to seek further, which is as it should be; but Hegel
sees also a further underlying philosophical problems. Hegel’s view
is that Kant responds to such “contradiction” with a kind of
“abstract negation”:
explanatory completeness would have to be entirely other or beyond
the kind of regress of conditions here, so that it is grasped first
in terms of what it is not,
as the un-conditioned; he
concludes that objects of reason must fall beyond our epistemic
limits. Hegel, by contrast, sees no grounds for abandoning the field
of the metaphysics of reason’s objects. For he sees rather a
determinate negation here:
specific failures of completeness demonstrate
specific results
concerning how better to give a positive understanding of the
objects of reason, and so how philosophical inquiry
must (given its
orientation by reason) proceed. For example, given the contradiction
in merely lawfully necessitated reality, the
Logic doesn’t just “try
something else”—as I put it, it is propelled in that it
“must turn instead to
teleology” (192).
Of course, this begins another series of
disputes with Kant, for which explanations will not fit here: Hegel
must defend the reality and knowability of what Kant calls “inner
purposiveness”, and Hegel must defend a greater explanatory
completeness of such teleology.
And Hegel argues that the greater explanatory completeness of
teleology requires realization in the lesser explanatory
completeness of the lawful—there must be something there to be
used on behalf of some
purpose or telos.
But, coming back to the propulsion issue, a natural outstanding
question concerns the status of the starting point that provides the
propulsion. This is why Hegel holds that his project will make sense
only if determinate negation—all the way to the lawful, to
teleology, and on from there—can in the end can circle back and
mediate, in the sense of justifying, the initial claim that there is
some complete form of reason in the world.
Space allows only brief replies to two further
questions. Pinkard notes Quine saying that he privileges physics
because he thinks that “nothing happens in the world … without some
redistribution of microphysical states” (1981, 98). Pinkard asks
whether I see Hegel as agreeing with Quine, or as more of a
Platonist. But I think that Quine is operating with such a
restricted metaphilosophy that direct comparison to Hegel is
unnecessary and unhelpful; substituting a better and more Hegelian
metaphilosophy dramatically changes the options. Quine is interested
in a privilege of physics
(“special deference”). But his
merely naturalist
conception of philosophy itself restricts what he can say about why.
He is so metaphilosophically constricted that what he ends up saying
expresses no privilege at
all. For it is
perfectly possible, given X’s and Y’s, that nothing changes without
a change in the X’s and yet
precisely the same is true of the Y’s. Privilege would be
expressed by views like: everything real is
ontologically dependent
on the physical. Or: the physical is the
reason in the world for
everything real. Note the illustration of Kant’s point above:
Quine’s “nothing happens” claim tries to be indifferent to such
metaphysics, but Quine’s interest in privilege shows him unable to
be indifferent. This is part of why I think comparisons to views in
a line of thought departing from Quine, Davidson, and so on, bring
metaphilosophical baggage that threatens to obscure rather than
clarify Hegel. In any case, we could now allow Quine’s claim that
every change is accompanied by physical change, while arguing that
something else is metaphysically prior in being responsible for
those physical changes. Matters are more complex than this in Hegel,
but he can for related reasons hold this: like teleology in general,
the absolute idea cannot be realized unless there is some
non-teleological substrate (unlike a form of Platonism denying
this); but the absolute idea, like teleology in general, is
metaphysically prior, in that it can be the trumping reason why
things happen as they do, and a more complete form of reason in the
world (as opposed to Quine’s privileging of the physical). My
response to Pinkard’s question about
Logic as a “realm of
shadows” is similar: yes, the topics of the
Logic also require
realization in some kind of “sensuous concretion” (WL 5:55/37); but,
no, that need not mean that the objects of the
Logic lack metaphysical
priority, or cannot be “explanatory
enough on their own” (xx).
3.
Brady Bowman raises
some questions, first, about teleology. At issue is my
interpretation and defense of Hegel’s rejoinder to Kant concerning
the inner purposiveness of life. I argue that the crucial point is
Hegel’s taking the concept or
Begriff as “the substance of life” (WL 6:472/678). I interpret
the point as related to Hegel’s reading of Aristotle on the species
as the form of an organism, and a formal cause. I also explain by
saying that this involves an intimacy of tokens (organisms) and
their type (species, form,
Begriff). Bowman is worried:
Tokens
are spatio-temporal particulars with causal powers, whereas types
are universals, i.e. non-spatio-temporal entities lacking causal
powers… to say that the type is
causally responsible
for (e.g. “brings about”)
any feature of the corresponding tokens amounts to a contradiction
in terms. (xx)
I think Hegel would
grant that, if that
ontology is correct, then nothing like a concept, universal or form
could be “the substance of life”, and inner purposiveness would be
an “incomprehensible mystery”
(WL 6:472/678)—which is what Kant wishes to show.
But Hegel is in great shape, in this respect: I think he has
excellent arguments, including some independent of the case of
teleology, for the conclusion that what “brings about” many
happenings crucially involves types in the sense of concepts or
kinds (Chapters 1-2). An example: what is responsible for the
planets rotating as they do is, in part, the nature of the
kind or “Begriff” of
matter, or “gravitation” being “the true and determinate concept of
material corporeality” (EN §269).
Bowman is also worried that my account of
teleology as realized in the non-teleological would leave teleology
of no explanatory relevance. He cites Hegel rejecting the view on
which the “non-organic” is “represented as existing independently
and for itself, and the organic is represented as an external
addition” (xx). I agree that Hegel rejects that view. But Hegel’s
position, as sketched above, is that non-organic lawful reality is
characterized precisely by dependence and lack of anything existing
“independently and for itself”. To imagine mechanism as capable of
trumping teleology in this way is to hold the view I call
“fundamentalist mechanism”, with mechanism paying the role of God in
a metaphysics; and Hegel has a good argument that mechanism is too
weak to play that role (101).
But this brings us now to Hegel’s absolute
idea. Before coming back to Bowman, I want to return briefly to
Tolley’s question on this topic. On my view, as he summarizes,
“[w]hat is free and thinking, what is the idea, is no one of its
instances, but rather the
unity of its instances as the realization of its concept” (xx).
And he cites me: ‘the absolute idea is no substrate’, ‘nor is it an
individual’, since ‘it is a process or movement, and one connecting
kind and particular individual’ (232). Tolley presses a dilemma:
does the metaphysical weight of distinguishing the absolute rest on
human individuals like us, thinking in some distinctive way; or does
it rest with the absolute idea in some independent sense, making
this itself a self-conscious individual, more comparable to
traditional theological conceptions in this respect? He has cited me
ruling out the latter in favor of the absolute idea as a self-moving
process. But if I say the former, then Tolley sees this as joining
interpreters like Pippin and Pinkard in a humanistic rather than
theological approach. But, to begin with, I don’t think the issue is
one of a humanist or a theological reading. For, on the one hand, I
argue that the Logic
itself makes no commitment concerning the individuals involved in
the absolute idea being either specifically human, or well-described
by the details in the
Philosophy of Spirit (230ff.). And, on the other hand, I argue
different contending interpretations create different tensions when
it comes to Hegel’s suggestions about the connection between the
absolute idea and theology. The Spinozist approach noted by Tolley,
like mine, will have both advantages and disadvantages here (265).
So I do not think that the options can be adjudicated just in terms
of which best captures the sense of Hegel’s comparisons with God;
they should be adjudicated on the basis of the metaphysical
arguments, and how these fit into a system. So the issue concerns
rather the relations between individuals and their concept or
Begriff. And Tolley’s
question about this seems to me to insist on a dualism that Hegel
would reject. I don’t think that the metaphysical weight in Hegel’s
metaphysics is going to be carried by
one thing or
another thing, but by a
distinctive interrelationship, or a system that precisely crosses
supposed gulfs. It is not as if we should expect that Hegel would
directly answer if pressed with a supposed dilemma concerning
whether the concrete universal is supposed to be concrete, or rather
universal; clearly the point is that it is both. Hegel’s arguments
about teleology, I point out in the book, require a form of this
“both” all forms of the idea will involve a system relating
individuals to their kind or concept (Begriff).
Further, Hegel's transitions focus on the limitations of a prior
topic. For example, noting the lack of a “totality of
self-determination” (WL 6:429/645) in “Chemism” is not a criticism
of the idea of such a self-determining system—it is an indication
that this is what is lacking insofar as we still have not yet
reached the absolute idea. So the story is similar with the
discussion of death to which Tolley points: at the end of “Life”,
“living individuality… on
account of its initial immediacy”
“perishes” in
“universality” “as the power” (EL §221). The point is not to argue
that individuals cannot carry more metaphysical weight. On the
contrary, this is a
limitation at this stage, falling short of the absolute idea: in
“Life” individuals are too powerless to carry their share of the
weight in a truly self-determining system. So the point is that
self-consciousness will allow individuals and their kind or concept
to share the metaphysical weight in a manner finally allowing a
self-determining system. The sense in which the system is
self-conscious will not be reducible to any independent facts about
its elements. We certainly should not expect the absolute idea to
involve the emergence of an independent divine standpoint beyond our
own, insofar as this would recreate the dualism between our own and
a divine form of knowledge—which Hegel famously, at least by the
time of the Logic, seeks
to overcome: “[t]he opposition … must be set aside” (EL §78).
Finally, there is Tolley’s connection to Pinkard and Pippin on
spirit. But here I myself argue that it is an advantage of my
reading that I can incorporate some of the benefits of their account
of spirit. I borrow some of what they have to say about Hegel on
self-consciousness, while giving a new account of the significance
of this theme for Hegel’s project—insofar as the key is not anything
like the role of this theme in an account of the conditions of the
possibility of experience or cognition of objects, but rather in a
metaphysics of reason in the world (section 9.1).
But this returns us to Bowman, who thinks—and
he has great company in this—that Hegel is a metaphysical monist; I,
again, do not. Bowman notes some passages that seem to suggest
oneness. I argue that there are passages that seem to suggest a
metaphysical monism on which the One explains or grounds everything
real—as well as passages that seem incompatible with this view
(261-2). So those on both sides need to explain the seeming
discrepancy. The monists I was concerned about in the book are those
who have what I call the “partial perspective” for reading Hegel:
from a partial perspective, things seem to be many; from a complete
perspective the whole is seen as only the One that explains or
grounds everything real. I give many reasons for denying that this
can be Hegel’s position. For example, it looks to rest on the kind
of dualism between a mediate, limited, finite intellect and an
infinite mind grasping reality immediately; that is again a dualism
Hegel rejects (EL §78). Further, the “partial perspective” strategy
conflicts with with Hegel’s argument that greater explanatory
completeness (as in teleology) requires realization in something
that is itself truly of lesser explanatory completeness (mechanism).
For this means that it cannot be the case, for Hegel, that
everything is completely explicable—he must and does reject the
principle of sufficient reason (PSR). It is not just that some
things must appear to be
incompletely explicable; they must really be, and so cannot be, when
seen from a complete perspective, completely in and grounded by any
One.
But I suspect that Bowman and I are not as far
apart here as first meets the eye. Bowman
cuts to the crux with a beautiful passage:
Monism
is the view that only one object truly
is or
exists, and Hegel clearly
seems to be saying that nothing other than the Absolute Idea is a
fully determinate unity and that therefore nothing other than the
Absolute Idea fully is,
i.e. fully possesses being.
That’s monism. (xx)
I am intrigued by
Bowman’s introduction of this “fully”: here we seem to get a
metaphysics of these
non-full entities, or
partials—as opposed to the what seems to me to be an
epistemological dodge in the partial-perspective strategy. This
gloss is surprisingly close to the view I attribute to Hegel,
namely: only the absolute idea is fully rational, substantial,
actual, and true. There is a slight difference here, insofar as I
think that this requires saying rather that there
are or
exist (fully) some things
that are not fully actual,
substantial, etc. And it
seems to me clear that this is more precisely what Hegel does say.
For example, Hegel famously equates the rational and the actual. But
he is at pains here to emphasize that there
is or
exists much that is not
fully actual: “[a]ny
sensible consideration of the world discriminates
… what truly merits the name ‘actuality’”
(EL §6). Lecture notes deny that we should “call every brain wave,
error, evil, and suchlike ‘actual’, as well as every existence” (EL
§6Zu).
But however that slight difference is resolved,
I think we are on the road to allowing that these partial entities
are not fully unified
with (or in, or similar)
the absolute idea. What I argue in the book is that the only grounds
for claiming defending such a metaphysical monism would have to be
some version of the PSR, used in some manner like Spinoza uses it.
But Hegel argues—powerfully, I try to show—that any such use of the
PSR will force the monist to an unacceptable elimination of all
finitude and all determinacy. So Hegel would say, first, that there
can be no good reason for thinking that the partials must be
in one absolute idea, or
unified with it, etc. And it is hard to see, second, how they could
be. For surely the absolute idea is completely explicable in terms
of itself, similar at least in some sense to Spinoza’s substance. So
I would think that something fully in or unified with the absolute
idea would be completely explicable thereby. So once we have a
metaphysical claim about these
partials (whether
partially existing, or partially substantial, etc.), I think the
break with Spinoza is sharp and decisive: First, a decisive break
with arguments from a PSR, needed, on Hegel’s account, for monism;
Hegel’s metaphysics includes things like the lawful, which are not
completely explicable—not by the absolute idea nor by anything at
all. Second, in Hegel’s metaphysics such things will be partially
“at the mercy of the unreason of externality”, and lawful reality
will “burdened … with externality” where “forms still remain
external to each other”.
The metaphysics of non-full entities, then, will have them at least
partially external to the
absolute idea, or partially non-unified by or with it. So this
metaphysics will allow some things that are neither the absolute
idea, nor in it, nor unified with it, nor similar. To borrow from
Bowman’s great passage, for the purposes of a friendly version of
the Hegelian determinate negation that we all seek to understand:
that’s not monism.
Abbreviations
AA
Kant,
Gesammelte Schriften
Akademie Ausgabe. Berlin: Reimer, later de Gruyter 1900ff.
ENC
Hegel, Enzyklopädie
der philosophischen Wissenschaften (1830),
in: GW 20. “R” = Remark, “A” = Addition.
GW
Hegel, Gesammelte Werke,
edited by the Academy of Sciences of Nordrhein-Westfalia, in
cooperation with the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft. Hamburg
1968ff.
TWA Hegel,
Werke in zwanzig Bänden:
Theorie Werkausgabe, edited by E. Moldenhauer, K. M. Michel.
Frankfurt am Main: 1969ff.
The rest need to be made uniform between the papers
Other Works Cited
Ameriks, K. 1985. “Hegel’s
Critique of Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy.” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 46(1): 1–35.
Beierwaltes, Werner 2004.
Platonismus und Idealismus. 2. Aufl. Frankfurt am Main.
Bird, A. (2007b).
“The Regress of Pure Powers?”
Philosophical Quarterly, 57, 513–34
Bowman, Brady 2012. Hegel and
the Metaphysics of Absolute Negativity. Cambridge.
Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford, Clarendon.
Garrett, D.
(1979). “Spinoza's Ontological
Argument.” The Philosophical Review 88/2: 198–223.
Halfwassen, Jens
2005. Hegel und der späte Neuplatonismus: Untersuchungen zur
Metaphysik des Einen und des Nous in Hegels spekulativer und
geschichtlicher Deutung. [= HEGEL-STUDIEN Beiheft 40]. 2. Aufl.
Hamburg.
Halfwassen, Jens
2004. Plotin und der Neuplatonismus. München.
Horstmann, Rolf-Peter 1984.
Ontologie und Relationen. Hegel, Bradley, Russell und die
Kontroverse über interne und externe Beziehungen. Königstein.
Hutchison, K. 1991. “Dormitive
Virtues, Scholastic Qualities, and the New Philosophies.”
History of Science
29: 245–78.
Kreines, J. 2015. Reason in
the World: Hegel’s Metaphysics and its Philosophical Appeal. OUP.
Lane, N. 2015. The vital question : energy, evolution, and the
origins of complex life.
Moore, A. W. (2012). The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics : Making
Sense of Things. New York, Cambridge University Press.
Pippin, R. 1989.
Hegel’s Idealism.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Plotinus 1918. On the One and Good, Being the Treatises of the Sixth
Ennead. Translated by Stephen Mackenna, B. S. Page. Boston.
Robinson, Howard 2014. "Substance",
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition),
Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/substance/>.
[Accessed 26.01.2016]).
Russell, B. 1927. The
Analysis of Matter. London: Kegan Paul.
Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action : elementary structures of
practice and practical thought. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University
Press.
Thompson, M. (2013). Forms of nature: ‘first’, ‘second’, ‘living’,
‘rational’ and ‘phronetic’. Freiheit : Stuttgarter Hegel-Kongress
2011. G. Hindrichs and A. Honneth. Frankfurt am Main, Vittorio
Klostermann: 701-735.
The regulative
ideal I seek, when it comes to systematic unity in
interpretations, is the version of this approach in Pippin
(1989); see especially pp. 7–8.
[2] See
Pippin’s use of Kant’s A158/B197 both at 1989, 33 and 2014,
148.
See the
A-Preface definition of metaphysics as conflict concerning
questions posed by our reason, but which it cannot answer.
Of course, Kant also seeks to transform (Bxxii) metaphysics
into a new form, and to answer questions within that
different kind of project.
Indeed, for
all of his emphasis on Hegel’s views on substance, it is
noteworthy that Jim’s own presentation does not draw at all
on Hegel’s own discussion of substantiality.
Among others,
on mechanism and explanation: Jaegwon Kim, David Chalmers,
David Armstrong; on monism and grounding: Jonathan Schaffer;
on teleology: Robert Cummins, Karen Neander, Ruth Millikan.
I will cite
Kant’s works according to the standard
Akademie Ausgabe
volume/pagination, except for the first
Critique which
I’ll cite according to the B-edition.
Since the
absolute totality of all possible experience ‘is not itself
an experience’ (4:328), it (this totality) is likewise not
given ‘in inner sense’ as a predicate of the thinking
subject.
At the outset
of the Dialectic, the ‘transcendental ideas’ themselves are
first introduced precisely as those ‘pure concepts of
reason’ which have their ‘origin [Ursprung]’ when ‘one
applies [anwendet]
the form of inferences of reason [syllogisms] to the
synthetic unity of
intuitions’, as that according to which ‘the use of the
understanding will be determined in the whole of the entire
[gesamte] experience’
(B378; my ital.).
Elsewhere
Hegel identifies this ‘going under’ with ‘begetting [Begattung]’,
which ‘extinguishes [erstirbt] the immediacy of living
individuality’ (WL 6:486).
“The quickest
way to explain the point here is to say that the three
requirements demand something that is (i) organized to
preserve itself through the activities of (ii) necessary
assimilation and (iii) reproduction” (94).
This seems to
be supported by the fact that Hegel begins the discussion of
“Life” in the Logic
under the heading, “The Living Individual.”
EN §326: “Der
chemische Prozeß ist so ein Analogon des Lebens; die innere
Regsamkeit des Lebens, die man da vor sich sieht, kann in
Erstaunen setzen. Könnte er sich durch sich selbst
fortsetzen, so wäre er das Leben; daher liegt es nahe, das
Leben chemisch zu fassen.”
“And the
pure mechanist view is supposed to be that powers always
require further support from below” (p. 43)
Ibid., p. 25: “Everything
lawful is so dependent as to be constituted by relation to
others; but nothing here is independent enough to support
the constitution of anything else.”
Ibid., pp. 193-194 :
“Hegel holds that lawful reality is relational through and
through. But Hegel also argues that we must be careful with
the view that the lawful is thoroughly relational, lest we
lose track of the degree to which, and the sense in which,
it is strange or distressing; we should recognize that what
we are defending is the reality of a kind of real
contradiction, albeit not one that rules out logical
possibility… On the contrary, the parts presuppose the
whole, which itself presupposes the differentiation of the
mutually external or different parts.”
Ibid., especially pp.
18, 122.
Note 19, p.
272, where Kreines partially rejects Pippin’s approach.
Kreines does
not, that is, seem to take the view of the dialectic as
progressing from less comprehensive to more comprehensive
views. We could call these the “box within a box” views of
dialectic: Being is one box, and it is included in another
box (Essence), which comprehends it and something more than
Being, and Essence is in turn placed in a larger box, which
comprehends both Being and Essence and something more.
Instead, Kreines uses the image of turtles stacked up on
each other, the last turtle being a turtle with a jetpack.
Just as the box within a box has to ask itself when there
are no more boxes to come, the turtle with a jetpack has to
ask whether that turtle can turn on the jetpack and fly
away, leaving the other turtles dangling.
See
Thompson (2008) and (2013),
and Foot, P. (2001).
Here is a citation from Hegel that particularly favors
Kreines’ interpretation: “Über
die Sache selbst ist fürs erste zu bemerken, daß jene
Gestalten von Anschauung, Vorstellung und
dergleichen dem selbstbewußten Geiste angehören, der
als solcher nicht in der logischen Wissenschaft betrachtet
wird. Die reinen Bestimmungen von Sein, Wesen und Begriff
machen zwar auch die Grundlage und das innere einfache
Gerüst der Formen des Geistes aus...
Allein diese konkreten Gestalten gehen die logische
Wissenschaft sowenig an als die konkreten Formen, welche die
logischen Bestimmungen in der Natur annehmen und welche
Raum und Zeit, alsdann der sich erfüllende Raum und Zeit
als unorganische Natur, und die organische Natur
sein würden. Ebenso ist hier auch der Begriff nicht als
Aktus des selbstbewußten Verstandes, nicht der subjektive
Verstand zu betrachten, sondern der Begriff an und für
sich, welcher ebensowohl eine Stufe der Natur
als des Geistes ausmacht.”
WL 6:257.
Obviously, a lot is going to hinge on how to interpret the
last sentence about how the concept in and for itself
constitutes a stage of nature and spirit.
There are many such citations in Hegel’s works: here is one
obvious instance: PhG
pp. 181-182: “Diese Kategorie nun oder
einfache Einheit
des Selbstbewußtseins und des Seins hat aber an sich
den Unterschied;
denn ihr Wesen ist eben dieses, im
Anderssein oder
im absoluten Unterschiede unmittelbar sich selbst gleich zu
sein. Der Unterschied
ist daher; aber vollkommen durchsichtig, und als ein
Unterschied, der zugleich keiner ist.”
EG
§384, p. 30: “Das
Absolute ist der Geist; dies ist die höchste Definition
des Absoluten.”
Kreines spells out this reason-constituting relation in
greatest detail in chapter 3 (esp. 97–103).
On Hegel’s conception of “objects” in relation to “the
Concept” see Horstmann
1984.
That entities considered at the mechanical level are
indifferent toward the characteristic marks of the kind to
which they belong is one of the chief failings of
mechanicism: for example, cp. Kreines [2015], 38–46.
In this context, consider that nothing about belonging to a
functional type (e.g. being a leaf) can guarantee that the
token in question will function as it ought. And that (we
might say) is because the type has no causal efficacy to
exercise. All the real causation is mechanical, and some
mechanically caused systems
happen to be
self-reproductively stable, so that relevantly similar
token-parts tend to be reproduced across successive wholes
of the right type. But there is no sense in which the type
is “responsible” for the organization of the token-wholes
and their token parts. — A further statement provokes
similar misgivings. Kreines says that the concrete universal
is a “type that
particularizes itself, giving the substance or nature of
independent individuals that differ in particular ways” (98,
emphasis added). That is indeed a characteristically
Hegelian way to talk, but what does it really mean for a
universal to “particularize itself,” and what kind of agency
do we ascribe to it in speaking thus? This way of talking
has a place in the Platonic tradition, of course, where
timeless universals are conceived as producing their own
spatio-temporal instantiations, but Kreines takes an
Aristotelian approach, explicitly concerned to construe
Hegel as not making “any demands at all about any sort of
supersensible substrate of nature transcending temporality”
(Kreines [2015], 103).
This is what is at stake in Hegel’s question about which of
the two concepts is higher, truer in itself, mechanism or
teleology (TWA 6:437–38).
On the relation of opposition between light and gravity cp.
ENC
§§
262, 275–277.
Kreines addresses the thorny issue of real contradictions in
chapter 10, sect. 2 (245–50). Here is my own suggestion to
those who balk at the idea that to instantiate an immanent
concept in the Hegelian sense is to exist as a real
contradiction: Any
realized concept, that is, any
idea (cp. ENC
§
242), is going to be structured as an individuated,
internally differentiated, kinetic whole; this totality is
governed by the polarity of opposing determinations whose
mutual tension, rather than self-destructing the way we
might expect a real contradiction to do, instead dynamizes
the system of integrated parts it constitutes. The flat-out
contradiction, devoid of really mediating terms, is a
feature of the abstract, i.e. the
as yet not fully
realized concept,
not of the idea,
i.e. the realized
Concept. So there is a way to embrace really real “immanent
concepts” without taking leave of the understanding.
However, it does force us to adjust our use of the term
“concept” to denote, in the strict sense, only such
relations that either instantiate the fully integrated,
realized structure of the Idea or which are intelligible as
its merely partial and incomplete (and hence also
self-contradictory) realizations.
Plotinus 1918, 237 (=VI 9, 1, 1–4). Cp. Halfwassen 2004,
32–34.
On Hegel’s relation to Neo-Platonism cp. Beierwaltes 2004,
144–153; Halfwassen
2005.
158;
WL
6:307–8/554–55
and WL 5:445–46/326.
Hegel
associates monads with indifference generally; see 175; WL
5:189/137; 6:410–13/632–34.
Tolley reads me as taking Kant’s idea of the “thinking
(experiencing) subject” (xx) to be that of a bare
substratum. For reasons noted above, I do not. My discussion
of Kant’s notion of a “final subject” guards against that
interpretation by noting that “I use the term ‘subject’ in
this chapter in the sense contrasting with ‘predicate,’ not
with ‘object’” (157).
16n20; cf. 142. Citation of
Ameriks 1985,
3.
There are
others on the table, discussed at in section 0.5.
Philosophy
“attests … to the inner drive of a rational insight that
goes further and alone gives human beings their dignity” (EL
8:13/pp. 6–7; cf. EL 8:38/p. 26, and Kant Ax).
I owe this
formulation to Bird (2007).
From
Le Malade Imaginaire,
translation from Hutchison (1991).
WL
6:562–3/745, and on this sections 7.3 and 10.2.
Section 8.3
and especially WL 6:452/663.
Section 10.1;
EL
§17, cf. PhG §6
E.g. “cannot
be comprehended” (KU 5:371)
Section 8.4;
McTaggart 1910, 275–76.
E.g. E1P11D3
and especially Garrett 1979.
Respectively
PN §248An;
(WL
6:434/649)