THE LIMITS OF METATHEORY AND THE INTERPRETATION OF HEGEL’S
SYSTEM
FINAL DRAFT
James Kreines
Please cite published version at Verifiche XLVI
(1), 2017, pp. 39-61.
http://www.hegelpd.it/hegel/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/Kreines-The-Limits-of-Metatheory-and-the-Interpretation-of-Hegels-System.pdf
My topic in this essay is Hegel’s ambition to
create a system of
philosophy, and what is required to interpret this specifically as a
system. Once we are clear about this, I argue, we can see what would
be involved in reading Hegel’s philosophy as a kind of metatheory.
This allows discerning the strongest way of developing a reading of
Hegel’s philosophy as a metatheory. But it also brings out reasons
to avoid even the strongest version of that approach, or reasons to
read Hegel’s philosophy as metaphysics rather than metatheory.
1. The Key to a System: Metaphilosophy
I begin with the very idea of a system of
philosophy, and with the question of what is specifically required
in building a system. Consider a familiar and simple example of a
specifically foundationalist system. This is not Hegel’s kind of
system, to be sure. It is just a simple example. The familiar idea
would be that what is needed for a system is a first principle that
is absolutely or immediately
certain, indubitable,
and infallible; we could
then safeguard all the further steps that will rest on this, and in
this way pass judgment on the legitimacy of all knowledge-claims.
But I think that this familiar way of beginning
already overlooks something required for a system. To see why,
imagine a metaphysician who claims not to care about our system. She
claims to be outside it, leaving the system incomplete. For she
claims not to care about certainty or infallibility at all. She is
simply indifferent to claims about a kind of
knowledge supposed to be
special in those ways. She leaves such topics to epistemologists,
while pursuing metaphysics.
But proponents of the foundationalist system
above probably meant, from the beginning, to exclude the possibility
of any such to claim to be outside the concerns of the system. They
will likely hold that epistemological issues about certainty are so
fundamental that all philosophers, at least,
must be concerned about
them, even if they do not realize this. So there is here another
commitment involved in building a system in this way: we need as
well a commitment concerning a kind of philosophical issue supposed
to be so fundamental that it is philosophically unavoidable. In this
example, we need the commitment that epistemological issues
concerning certainty are fundamental in this way. I call this a
metaphilosophical commitment, because it is a commitment concerning
what is fundamental to philosophy itself. So further reflection on
the simple example shows that a metaphilosophical commitment was
organizing our simple system from the beginning: it told us where to
begin, namely, with something certain; and it told us how to link
the elements of a system together, namely, by transition rules
preserving this certainty.
Now this is just one example. I have argued on
similar grounds that a philosophical system generally requires such
an organizing metaphilosophical commitment.
So when we look to the history of philosophy and find an attempt at
a philosophical system—as in the case of Hegel—it is important to
consider what metaphilosophical commitment is supposed to organize
or unify that system.
If we do not consider the question of
metaphilosophy, then this can cause mistakes. For an example, I look
to Richard Rorty’s work, work, beginning with
Philosophy Mirror of Nature.
Rorty here contrasts systematic and edifying philosophy:
Great
systematic philosophers are constructive and offer arguments. Great
edifying philosophers are reactive and offer satires, parodies,
aphorisms. (269)
Furthermore, Rorty argues that systematic
philosophy includes a commitment about what philosophical questions
are most fundamental: it “centers in epistemology”, and
“[s]ystematic philosophers want to put their subject on the secure
path of a science” (269-70). Systematic philosophy is fundamentally
concerned with security, or certainty, sufficient to provide
epistemological foundations. But Rorty argues that such attempts
must go awry. Systematic philosophy is an “attempt to answer
questions of justification by discovering new objective truths”.
And:
The
primal
error of systematic philosophy has always been the notion
that such questions are to be answered by some new ("metaphysical"
or "transcendental") descriptive or explanatory discourse… (383)
So there is a metaphilosophical claim that
this aim is fundamental to systematic philosophy, and yet that aim
cannot be achieved; thus there is an error at the very heart of
systematic philosophy. And this suggests that what we need to do is
to turn toward edifying philosophy. So I see something like this
line of reasoning at work:
RR1:
Systematic philosophy is fundamentally concerned with establishing
the immediate certainty of epistemological foundations.
RR2: It
is hopeless and useless to try to establish immediately certain
epistemological foundations for all knowledge claims.
RR3:
Thus, systematic philosophy is hopeless and useless.
Before coming to Hegel, I will take the simpler
example of my own views about this line of argument. I do not mean
to argue for these views here, just to have an example of some views
to interpret. So my position is this: I think that RR2 is correct;
that kind of project is
hopeless. But I think that RR1 is mistaken: Systematic philosophy
that is “constructive” and “offers arguments” need not be most
fundamentally concerned with epistemological certainty or
foundations, or even concerned with this at all. I will argue below
that Hegel is one example of a systematic philosopher who does not
fit this mold; but I think there are many. So I entirely reject
Rorty’s pessimistic conclusion about systematic philosophy itself.
But now imagine an interpreter engaging with
what I have said:
Interpreter: Kreines has
a Rortyan philosophy.
Kreines:
No.
Interpreter: Yes. Kreines
agrees with Rorty on the absolutely crucial RR2.
Kreines: But I disagree
about the conclusion; I defend the prospects for systematical
philosophy.
Interpreter: True. I only
meant to single out the basic thrust of Kreines’ philosophy. But it
is true that there is an inconsistency there, a kind of civil war
within Kreines’ view. In accepting RR2, the basic thrust of his
thinking is moving forward in a Rortyan direction, toward
recognition of a primal error at the heart of systematic philosophy.
But Kreines elsewhere backslides into a failure to see the
implications of this primal error.
Needless to say, I think this interpreter is
mistaken. Perhaps, for all I have really demonstrated here, Rorty is
right and I am wrong. But I do not think my position is inconsistent
in this way. I don’t think my position is akin to Rorty’s at all.
Granted, if we assume
Rorty’s metaphilosophical standpoint, then what I have said can seem
to be at odds with itself. For I have defended systematic
philosophy; and yet I might seem to have agreed, in accepting RR2,
that systematic philosophy contains a “primal error”. But this is my
point in rejecting RR1: I reject Rorty’s metaphilosophical
standpoint altogether. If what I write is interpreted from the
metaphilosophical standpoint that I reject, then misunderstanding is
inevitable.
Now my interest here is really in the
interpretation of Hegel. So I note that Rorty’s interpretation of
Hegel does see a kind of civil war within his thinking. On the one
hand, there are at least two respects in which Rorty sees Hegel’s
thinking as moving in the right directions. First, Hegel is rightly
opposed to immediately certain foundations in epistemology, and so
manages to avoid the ambition of “grounding”
other disciplines. Second, Hegel does not attempt to separate
philosophy from other disciplines, but writes philosophy in a way
that engages with other domains. He “made philosophy too popular,
too interesting, too important, to be properly professional” (135).
However, Rorty also sees Hegel as tragically failing to draw the
implication he could and should draw, namely, a systematic
philosophy—that is “constructive” and offers “arguments”—is doomed.
If Hegel were true to himself, he would have turned instead toward
“satires, parodies, aphorisms” (269). A good indication of this is
Rorty’s later position on Hegel’s
Logic:
My
favorite remark of Kierkegaard's about Hegel is that if he had ended
books like Science of Logic … with the remark that "this was
all just a thought experiment," he would have been the greatest
thinker who ever lived. … as it was, he was a buffoon. The epithet
is too harsh, but the spirit of the remark seems right. (1995,
221n2)
Perhaps better, given Rorty’s gloss on
edifying philosophy, would be concluding the
Logic with an aphorism
indicating that the preceding volumes were a satire or parody of
systematic philosophy. In any case, looking at Hegel through the
lens of Rorty’s metaphilosophical commitments, we certainly do find
that Hegel’s work is at odds with itself.
Should we conclude from this that Hegel’s work
is really at odds with itself? Not on my view. For the appearance of
a civil war can arise simply because we choose to view Hegel through
the lens of a foreign metaphilosophical commitment. What we should
conclude is that understanding Hegel’s system requires additional
reflection on metaphilosophy—reflection on what philosophy really
is, and really can be. And it requires attention to what
metaphilosophy really animates Hegel’s own attempt at a system. I
think this always a danger for interpreters of the history of
philosophy: we will always be tempted to view history through the
lens of a metaphilosophical view that is implicit in philosophical
work popular today.
Another way to make these points would be as a
way of giving specific content to the distinction between the spirit
and the letter of a philosophical system. The unifying spirit is
provided by metaphilosophical commitment. But there are always
innumerably many ways to attend to the letter in a manner that
contradicts the spirit. There is here a problem that seems
inescapable for those who write philosophy: one must write out all
of the parts in order to execute the whole of an organized
philosophical project; but regardless of how one does this, each
part will be such as could be read by interpreters in a manner
contradicting the spirit of the project.
I draw four conclusions. First, a system of
philosophy requires organization by metaphilosophy that will give it
focus, and connect its individual arguments together into a broader
project or system. Second, the projects of two philosophers might
share any number of individual
claims without being
similar projects at all,
insofar as they can be organized by opposing metaphilosophies.
Third, interpretation of a systematic philosopher requires attention
to the metaphilosophy that animates or organizes her project.
Fourth, interpreting a system through the lens of an ill-fitting
metaphilosophy can give the false appearance of a conflict or civil
war within that system.
2. Hegel’s Philosophy as Metatheory?
Now I want to examine in light of the above a
further question: Should we interpret Hegel’s philosophy as
metatheory? I think that we can now delineate the best of such
interpretations, but also a reason to worry about any such
interpretation.
To define metatheory, I would look to the
distinction between an object-level and meta-levels. Sometimes we
talk or write about things specifically insofar as they are in turn
about something. We can ask, for example, about thoughts, how it is
that they are about anything at all. Where we have discourse about
things insofar as they are about something, we have meta-level
discourse. Otherwise we have object-level discourse. So a philosophy
that is meta-theoretical would be a philosophy about something,
specifically insofar as that something is about something. This
could be philosophy focused on pursuit of the very possibility of
aboutness: how is it that claims, thoughts, theories, etc. are
about anything at all? Or
it could be focused on questions that depend on this aboutness. For
example, it could be a philosophy focused on the question of what it
would be for thoughts or claims about something to amount to
knowledge of that
something. And so on.
Now we can ask the question about Hegel: is his
philosophy a metatheory? But the results of my first section, above,
suggest that we must take care in understanding the question. One
way to understand it would be as this question: does Hegel make any
meta-level claims? Or, does his philosophy contain metatheoretical
elements. This seems to me easy to answer: of course it does. For
example, his criticisms of Empiricism (§37-9) include criticisms of
empiricist epistemology, or empiricist accounts of what makes
certain thoughts or claims about objects amount to knowledge of
those objects.
But this is, at best, a misleading
interpretation of the question. This is akin to asking whether my
philosophy is Rortyan, and then answering that it is on account of
the claim from Rorty with which I agree. And we know that noting
similar claims in two different philosophical projects has the
potential to lead us into mistakes about the spirit of the projects.
So just noting that Hegel’s philosophy includes some claims that
would be at home in a metatheoretical project is not enough to
establish that it is best understood as metatheory. The crucial
question is rather this: is Hegel’s
project is itself a
project in metatheory? And that is to ask: is Hegel’s project
organized by a commitment to the fundamentality of metatheory, or
some specific metatheoretical problem or issue?
If there is a strong way to read Hegel’s
philosophy as meta-theory, then it would have to answer
these questions in the
affirmative. But what cannot make for a strong approach here is to
read Hegel’s philosophy as metatheory specifically because one is
oneself attracted to philosophical projects organized around
metatheory. One might well think that this is the best way for
theoretical philosophy to proceed. Or even that it is the only way
for there to be anything promising for theoretical philosophy to do.
And one might then be very happy to find claims in Hegel which,
undoubtedly, address metatheoretical issues. Still, if a focus on
metatheory does not organize Hegel’s project, then reading him in
light of such a focus cannot be charitable, no matter how strongly
one favors metatheory; for reading him in light of a foreign
organizing principle can only make his system appear to be at odds
with itself.
We do, however, have a very strong reading of
Hegel’s philosophy as metatheory. The best case, I think, is the one
pioneered in Robert Pippin’s pathbreaking book,
Hegel’s Idealism (1989).
One thing that makes this reading so powerful is that, although the
issues are not raised in these terms, it contains a strong argument
concerning a metaphilosophical commitment that is supposed to
organize Hegel’s systematic project. Hegel is supposed to take as
“basic to his project” issues with a unifying “common theme”—“the
argument that any subject must be able to make certain basic
discriminations in any experience in order for there to be
experience at all” (1989, 7-8). So this would be a philosophical
project organized by a commitment to the fundamentality of issues
concerning the possibility of experience. These are metatheoretical
issues, in the sense that they ask what it is for a state of a
subject to amount to experience
of some object. And Hegel
is supposed to borrow a Kantian approach, insofar as he agrees with
Kant that these issues must be resolved by appeal to something that
the subject actively does. This is what is supposed to organize the
whole of Hegel’s philosophy, making the parts all variations on a
central Kantian theme:
…his own
theory of the Begriff,
and indeed the relation between the
Begriff and reality, or
the basic position of his entire philosophy, should be understood as
a direct variation on a crucial Kantian theme, the "transcendental
unity of apperception.” (6)
Now this basic approach has been extremely
influential, even while much of the terminology has changed over the
years. These passages refer to issues about the possibility of
experience of objects.
But we could consider instead the possibility of any intentional
relation to objects at all. Or we could consider the possibility of
normative concept use, or the like. And one might take an approach
to all of these issues that is Kantian, in the above sense, holding
that we must account for these possibilities in terms of a kind of
activity. I think all of these approaches has flourished within the
space opened up by Pippin’s arguments. On any such account, Hegel’s
philosophy would be, at base, a meta-theory: a theory about how
object-level theories relate to their objects.
I think this approach is stronger than its
critics tend to recognize. In particular, critics sometimes offer a
complaint along these lines: yes, this metatheory is part of what
Hegel is doing; but it is important that Hegel is
also engaging with
object-level issues in metaphysics. But, first of all, this
criticism offers no rival understanding of the systematic unity of
Hegel’s project: it rests content with saying that Hegel is doing
this and also that. The
big challenge, in reading Hegel, is to explain what gives unity to
the many topics he addresses. To do that, we cannot rest content at
the end of the day with an “X and also Y” formulation. So on this
score, the above metatheoretical reading comes out stronger than the
criticism: it has a unifying explanation of the project.
Furthermore, there is no reason that this metatheoretical approach
cannot acknowledge that Hegel engages object-level issues in
metaphysics. The basic claim is not that Hegel addresses only one
kind of issue. Clearly Hegel addresses a great many kinds of issues.
The question is rather what issues he takes as fundamental, so as to
organize his approach to all other issues into a system. So the
strongest metatheoretical approach can allow that Hegel engages with
metaphysics; what it must hold is that Hegel answers metaphysical
questions, if at all, then specifically on the basis of his concern
with more metatheoretical issues.
However, while this metatheoretical approach is
stronger than some critics recognize, I do not myself share this
approach to Hegel. Here I will give three drawbacks that dissuade
me.
First of all, we have not yet located in Hegel
any supposed argument for
the claim that metatheory is fundamental in philosophy. As it
happens, I think Hegel himself explains well how such an argument
would have to work, attributing this argument to “the Critical
philosophy”. But Hegel does so in the course of
criticizing the argument.
Hegel’s sketch of the argument for the priority
of metatheory is this:
It is
one of the main viewpoints of the Critical philosophy that,
prior to setting about to acquire cognition of God, the essence of
things, etc., the faculty of cognition itself would have to
be examined first in order to see whether it is capable of achieving
this…
I take the argument under discussion to be as
follows: All philosophy must think about or cognize something,
whether this is God, or essence, or whatever. But whatever
philosophy is going to think about, it will have thereby raised the
question of how it is capable of achieving thought or cognition of
such objects at all. So philosophy requires a metatheoretical
account of how cognition achieves this aboutness. And such
metatheory is fundamental to philosophy.
But, as I said, Hegel articulates this argument
in order to criticize it. In particular, the worry about cognition
achieving a relation to its objects, if really so important, would
apply on the meta-level as well. That is, it would equally manifest
as a worry that cognition might not be capable of taking itself as
an object. So if it were
true that we must not attempt to cognize objects on some domain
until we have a prior metatheoretical account of how this is
possible, then it would also be true that we must avoid the attempt
at a metatheoretical account of the congition of an object until we
have a meta-meta-level account of its possibility. And then the same
point applies there too and on an infinitely ascending series of
meta-levels. Hegel makes a striking comparison here: the case of the
fundamentality of metatheory is “as incoherent as the Scholastic's
wise resolution to learn to swim, before he ventured into the water”
(§10A; cf. PhG §73-4). And this seems to me a powerful argument
against the case for the
fundamentality of meta-theory to philosophy. Hegel shows that there
is not in fact good reason to think that philosophy needs or
requires to be built around a meta-level theory of the relation of
thought to objects. Hegel’s intended lesson is clear: we should
instead jump in the water. That is, some other kind of issue must
organize a philosophical project—not any issue that would give a
supposed priority to metalevel reflection. Given the above, it
should be obvious that this does not mean avoiding metatheorteical
issues; I have noted that Hegel does not avoid them. Rather, the
fundamental issues of philosophy will be indifferent to any
distinction between object and meta-levels, and will include
metaphysical issues on the object level about such topics as God and
the essences of things. And that is a first reason why, on my view,
we should not read Hegel’s philosophy as a metatheory: he himself
rejects the required case for the fundamentality of metatheory.
Now I have written about the swimming passage
before,
so here I will push on to second and third reasons to avoid reading
Hegel’s philosophy as metatheory. The second is an extension of the
first. Proponents of a meta-theoretical Hegel will see Hegel as
rejecting competing philosophies on grounds that they cannot give a
satisfactory resolution of a supposedly fundamental problem on a
meta-level. That is, competitors are supposed to lack a satisfactory
account of how cognition relates to objects. For example, those who
read Hegel in this way can compare his philosophy to contemporary
anti-realism and rejections of so-called “metaphysical realism”.
We can compare Hilary Putnam’s argument: “metaphysical realism” is
supposed to fail to adequately account for
reference; thus Putnam
complains that metaphysical realists assume a “magical theory of
reference”. Since we should require a better theory of reference—a
kind of metatheory—we should reject metaphysical realism, and prefer
internalism; we should conclude that “'Objects' do not exist
independently of conceptual schemes” (Putnam 1981, 49-52). Note that
this like of argument privileges the metatheoretical issue of
reference: the topic is supposed to be so fundamental that, if a
theory cannot account for this, the theory can be rejected. But,
even if successful to this point, systematic pursuit of this line of
thought would have to eventually include a demonstration that
internalism can provide a satisfying metatheoretical account of
reference. Otherwise one might just as well conclude that such a
metatheory is equally difficult for both metaphysical realism and
internalism, resulting in no privilege for the latter.
I infer from this that, if we read Hegel’s
project as metatheory, then then we would have to show that Hegel
eventually himself distinguishes and privileges a meta-level,
ascends to that meta-level, and defends a positive theory there. We
cannot go on to say that Hegel does not provide such a theory, for
that will be reason to think that the focus of the system was never
really on metatheory to begin with. But we cannot read Hegel’s
philosophy as metatheory, in this way, because he himself rejects
the idea of a dualism between object-level and meta-level. We can
see this in the citation above. The viewpoint of the critical
philosophy, discussed in that passage, is that philosophical
problems concerning cognition emerge on the object-level, whose
solution requires an ascent to the meta-level. But Hegel’s response
is that the meta-level would be no different with respect to the
issues: if those problems were so pressing to begin with, then they
will emerge as well on the meta-level. And if they do not prevent
theorizing on a meta-level, then they also should not prevent
proceeding directly to the object-level, or jumping right into the
water. On Hegel’s account, those who privilege metatheory would like
a dualism between object- and meta-level to do a great deal of
philosophical work that it cannot in fact do. So I do not think that
Hegel could organize each step of his system specifically by means
of the goal of defending a positive theory
specifically on the
meta-level.
A third and last reason to avoid reading
Hegel’s philosophy as metatheory focuses on the end of the
Science of Logic.
Consider some of the steps Hegel goes through: mechanism, chemism,
teleology, life, and then there is cognition and the absolute idea.
These conclusions seem to me to involve, at very least, some
metaphysical claims on the object level. For example, the “Life”
chapter argues, at least in part, that there are organisms, truly
characterized by inner purposiveness.
I see two ways that a reading of Hegel’s
philosophy as metatheory might deal with such concluding,
object-level metaphysical claims; but neither seems to me prmosing.
On the one hand, there is the approach that Pippin takes in
Hegel’s Idealism (1989):
He says that even if there are object-level claims here, they go
beyond the conclusions of Hegel’s argument in the
Logic: they
are not
‘playing any significant role in the position defended’, which
operates on a ‘metalevel’.
Here a meta-theoretical reading threaten to force us to see
Hegel’s work as again at odds with itself: one strand of Hegel
sticks to his argument, within metatheory; but another strand falls
back into claims that do not play a role in that argument, or
object-level metaphysical claims. But we saw above that this
appearance of a civil war can be the result of reading a
philosophical project through the lens of a foreign organizing
commitment. In this case, reading Hegel’s philosophy as metatheory
results in a picture of Hegel as internally conflicted. I argued
above that this is good reason to consider different approaches to
the commitment that organizes a philosophical project.
On the other hand, a metatheoretical reading
could take a different approach here. It could agree that there are
object-level metaphysical conclusions drawn at the end of the
Logic, while holding that
these conclusions are drawn on the basis of the more fundamental
metatheoretical reflection on the possibility of cognition or
experience of any object. I think that this is the strategy Pippin
favors in recent work.
I see in turn two possibilities here: metaphysical conclusions about
the object of cognition,
as such, and metaphysical conclusions about the
subject of cognition. One
possibility is that consideration of the possibility of cognition of
any object might get you a
metaphysics of all objects. But Hegel’s point at the conclusion
of the Logic is not that
every object is alive, or
characterized by inner purposiveness. Nor is it that objects must be
alive in order for it to be possible for us to judge or experience
them. On the contrary, Hegel argues that organisms are composed of
non-organic parts, and that we can have knowledge of this.
The other possibility is that metatheory generates metaphysical
conclusions about the subject
of cognition. For instance, perhaps one could argue that we are
creatures who can cognize objects, and that we ourselves and our
cognition must be characterized by a metaphysical spontaneity.
But this route seems destined to end in a dualism separating the
metaphysics of the cognizing
subject and the metaphysics of the
objects of its judgments.
And this neither fits. For the concluding chapters of the
Logic are neither about
the metaphysics of all objects, nor are they built around a basic
dualism between subject and object. Rather, Hegel’s conclusion
stresses gradual, distinct metaphysical steps, from the lawful
necessitation of mechanism and chemism, to the teleology of life, to
cognition. So even if the metatheoretical approach to Hegel could
support some metaphysics, I do not see how it could hope generate
Hegel’s metaphysics.
And so I think that there are three excellent
reasons to worry about even the strongest approach to reading
Hegel’s philosophy as metatheory.
3. An Alternative: Metaphysics and the Dialectic
It remains to explain why I think there is a
better approach to Hegel’s project. In particular, I think the
challenges of interpreting Hegel’s system suggest the superiority of
reading Hegel’s philosophy not as metatheory, but as metaphysics.
There can be no question of adequately defending this other option
here; this is the aim of my book (2015). Here what is important is
to show at least some indication that reading the system as
organized by a focus on metaphysics improves matters specifically
with respect to the problems concerning Hegel’s systematicity, and
specifically relative to the drawbacks of a metatheoretical
interpretation.
I propose that Hegel takes as fundamental some
metaphysical issues, drawn specifically from Kant’s Transcendental
Dialectic of the first
Critique. Yet again, the point is not to say that Hegel avoids
epistemology, but that he radically and systematically transforms
everything else, including epistemology, in light of fundamentally
metaphysical issues. We can say that the basic issues concern
grounds or conditions, and ultimately the completeness of grounding
or “the unconditioned”. I think that this means an interest in
whatever is such that we could appeal to in order to
explain something, and
ultimate in whatever is such that we can appeal to it in order to
explain something completely.
So we could explain by saying that the fundamental topic of
Hegel’s project is the metaphysics of complete explanation.
Note that this topic is not specifically
meta-theoretical. It applies perfectly naturally at the object
level, where we seek objects in the world to which we can appeal in
explaining things. But it can also be pursued on the meta-level,
where we might seek whatever it is in our cognition that explains
how cognition relates to objects. Here the fundamental philosophical
issues are indifferent to a dualism between the meta- and
object-level; the former is not eliminated, but the dualism is
overcome.
Now Kant argues that, although there are
metaphysical issues concerning the unconditioned, of basic interest
to our reason itself, our attempts at theoretical philosophy in
response generate contradictions, preventing us from answering
questions that are metaphysical in that particular sense.
But Hegel seeks to show that the contradictions of Kant’s Dialectic
teach a different lesson, about how to fix metaphysics in that same
sense involving the objects of reason. So Hegel’s project in the
Logic is not a
meta-theory of how cognition relates to objects—not the kind of
theory Hegel sees in Kant’s deductions from the Transcendental
Analytic. Nor is it like Spinoza’s pre-Kantian metaphysics. The
organizing focus of Hegel’s project is more distinctive: it is to
reconstruct metaphysics on grounds of the strongest criticism of
metaphysics, from the contradictions of Kant’s Dialectic.
Looking back to the conclusion of the
Logic, I want to single
out as an example the ‘Chemism’ chapter.
Hegel is not here specifically addressing what we would classify
under the heading of chemistry; he is addressing any distinct
natural kinds that fundamentally interact in a manner necessitated
lawfully.
Hegel defends this conclusion: to be this kind of thing is to
interact lawfully in certain ways with other kinds. In his terms,
each kind of lawful thing “is not comprehensible from itself, and
the being of one object is the being of another” (SL 12:149/646).
Such a natural kind is, first, such as can be comprehended. It is
not an object of of sense perception, but of conceptual thinking. It
is “comprehensible” or “begreiflich”. This is one sense, at least,
it is a form of “concept” or “Begriff”. But it is, second, not
comprehensible from itself.
So this is a form of metaphysical holism: the being
of kind X is such that, to comprehend it, one must think in
terms of its lawful interaction with kind Y. And then the same
applies to Y, and so on, to a whole lawfully interconnected network.
So the “determinateness” of anything lawful is just one “moment”
of a larger comprehensible “whole”, of the
concept of the whole: it
“is the concrete moment of the individual concept of the whole which
is the universal essence, the real kind [Gattung]
of the particular objects” (SL 12:149/646).
Now this seems to me clearly a
metaphysical form of
holism: the point is about the very
being of a lawfully
interacting object, or the what-it-is-to-be that object. The point
does not distinguish a
meta-level, and then limit itself to a semantic holism on that
level, or a claim that
meanings of different terms are dependent on others. Nor does it
limit itself to an epistemological holism, holding that the
justification for any claim always rests on others within a web of
belief. Nor do I see any reason for thinking that this metaphysics
is present as secondary to a point that epistemological, semantic,
or otherwise meta-theoretical. The point is not that we should
accept this metaphysical holism because we need it to give a
meta-theoretical account of how cognition relates to objects. The
metaphysical results seem just as much part of the fundamental aims
of the Logic itself.
Again, the very being of
one lawful thing depends on the
being of others.
So far, then, the approach to Hegel’s project
via metaphysics seems to fit well the focus of the chapters near the
end of the Logic. On this
account, Hegel’s focus near the crucial transition to the final
section on “The Idea” is on metaphysics, and that is unsurprising
because that is indeed (on this account) the focus that is supposed
to organize the larger project.
But can this explain as well how taking
metaphysics as fundamental might provide the actual organization,
connecting and unifying these topics at the end of the
Logic? I think that the
answer is “yes”. To get a sense of this, we need to note that Hegel
sees a contradiction within the lawful reality of chemism. On my
account, there are two sides to this: the sense in which Hegel
famously leaves a real contradiction in the world, and the sense in
which contradiction forces the
Logic from one topic to
the next, systematically connecting everything together.
To see the first sense of contradiction,
imagine that current natural science were to recognize three basic,
lawfully interacting kinds, X, Y, Z. What
is X? What fixes its
identity?
One can say that X just is the kind defined by attraction (for
example) to Y. But this would seem to defer the fixing of identity
to Y, raising the question about it. And then it does seem
problematic if the same reasons force us to say the same of Y, and
so on to all physical reality. Some will say that this is logically
impossible. Sometimes they put the point by saying that there cannot
be relations without relata. Russell finds the impossibility
obvious:
There
are many possible ways of turning some things hitherto regarded as
“real” into mere laws concerning the other things. Obviously there
must be a limit to this process, or else all the things in the world
will merely be each other’s washing. (1927, 325)
Some philosophers continue to see here reason
that there would have to be some more independent character to
physical reality, even if natural science could never attain
knowledge of it. But the pull in that direction is that of what
Hegel calls “the metaphysics of the understanding”: the seeming need
for something underlying the relational properties here, so that we
could bundle all of the relational properties, and say in
independent terms what they are properties of. Hegel thinks that
physicists tend to give in to the temptation, resulting in their
moving beyond physics and into philosophy and metaphysics—but in
unfortunate ways. For example, after the successful discovery of
gravitation, a philosophical mistake follows: “a physical meaning of
independent forces is
given” (EN §270A). We imagine physical objects as having independent
being, and then want to give independence to forces by thinking of
them similarly. Hegel’s position is that natural science would be
better off being indifferent to such considerations. Philosophers,
meanwhile, should recognize that there is a kind of Antinomy
contradiction here, to which Russell is reacting, but it is not
something that needs solving by hidden substrata; it is something
like a contradiction, but rather one that expresses the correct
metaphysics of merely lawful reality.
Now that claim about the reality of
contradiction is difficult, and requires more attention to resolve.
My point here, however, is to turn to the related sense in which
attention to contradiction is supposed to move the
Logic along,
systematically connecting everything together. Here the key is that
lawful reality now looks explanatorily incomplete.
But Kant and Hegel agree that theoretical inquiry is always
guided by the aim of the unconditioned, or completeness of
explanation, so that inquiry cannot be indifferent to this. Thus
Kant says: “So-called
indifferentists,
to the extent that they think anything at all, always
unavoidably fall back into metaphysical assertions, which they yet
professed so much to despise” (Ax). I like to compare here the
famous joke from Molière:
I am
asked by the learned doctor for the cause and reason that opium
makes one sleep. To this I reply that there is a dormitive virtue in
it, whose nature it is to make the senses drowsy.
My idea here is that inquiry proceeds based,
in part, on a commitment to reject such dormitive-virtue
explanations as empty, and instead to seek something in terms of
which we could explain more completely. But then theoretical inquiry
would contradict its own premises if it concluded that physical
reality is exhausted by these three forces that we have found, while
professing indifference to explanations beyond the fact that x’s do
what they do on account of this being the nature of kind X, and so
on everywhere. Hegel sees this threatened contradiction as a central
philosophical problem. And Hegel’s view is that Kant responds to
such “contradiction” with a kind of “abstract negation” (WL
12:246/745): Kant concludes that greater explanatory completeness
would have to be something entirely beyond the regress of conditions
within the lawful, so that greater completeness is grasped first in
terms of what it is not,
as the un-conditioned;
and Kant concludes that such objects satisfying to reason would have
to fall beyond our epistemic limits, so that metaphysical
conclusions concerning the unconditioned would be impossible for us.
Hegel, by contrast, sees the contradiction as no reason to
abandoning the metaphysics that considers reason’s objects. For
Hegel finds determinate negation here:
specific failures of
completeness within the lawful demonstrate
specific results
concerning a better, positive understanding of the objects of
reason. And these are conclusions that force philosophy, given its
orientation by reason, to move forward in a specific direction. In
this particular case, the contradiction in merely lawfully
necessitated reality is supposed to show that philosophy must turn
its attention to teleology and inner purposiveness.
And we can see in this way how Hegel hopes to
follow a unified kind of basic metaphysical issue through
completely or
systematically to
positive conclusions at the end of the
Logic. In particular, he
aims to justify a reconception of what Kant thinks of as “the
unconditioned”. To be conditioned, on Hegel’s account, will be to be
something that does not determine itself. So the unconditioned will
no longer be understood negatively, in terms of the lack of
conditioning; it will rather be a kind of
self-determination. Thus
what is lacking in Chemism or lawful reality is that, although we
have here a system or linked totality, it is not “it is not yet for
itself” a “totality of self-determination” (WL 12:152/645). And
pursuit of this continual refinement in the metaphysics of
explanation will lead Hegel through multiple stages, rather than
leaving him with a basic dualism. The point will not be that a
cognizing subject is self-determining, and all objects of cognition
merely determined. The series of contradictions will lead the
Logic through stages of
increasingly more complete forms of self-determining. So these
metaphysical concerns not only organize the topics addressed in the
Logic, but they give it
the specifically non-dualist organization that we in fact see at the
end of the Logic.
4. Conclusions
In this paper, I have, first, called attention
to the challenges of interpreting a philosophical system. In
particular, a system requires a metaphilosophical commitment that
will organize its parts into a coherent whole. So finding this
organizing commitment is a central task in an interpretation of a
philosophical system. Second, I have argued that reading Hegel as
meta-theory consequently requires attributing to him a commitment to
the fundamentality of metatheoretical issues. There is a way to do
this, but there are also three important worries about even the best
way of doing it. Finally, I have argued that these drawbacks do not
affect similarly the idea of reading Hegel’s project as
fundamentally metaphysical in focus. I conclude, then, that it is
best to interpret Hegel’s philosophy not as meta-theory, but as
metaphysics.
Abbreviations
HEGEL: Encyclopedia cited by § number, with
‘An’ indicating Anmerkung and
‘Zu’ indicating the Zusatz. All other
references to Hegel’s writings are given by
volume and page number Hegel,
Gesammelte Werke, edited
by the Academy of Sciences of Nordrhein-Westfalia, in cooperation
with the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft.
Hamburg
1968ff. I use the following abbreviations
and translations:
SL: Hegel’s Science of Logic. 2010.
Translated by G. di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
EL:
Encyclopaedia Logic. 2010. Translated by K. Binkmann and D. O.
Dahlstrom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
KANT: Aside from references to the Critique
of Pure Reason, all references to
Kant’s writings are given by volume and page
number of the Akademie edition
of Kant’s Gesammelte
Schriften (de Gruyter, Berlin 1902-). I use these
abbreviations and translations:
A/B: Critique of Pure Reason, translations
from Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge, 1998.
Other Works Cited
Bird, A. 2007. “The Regress of Pure Powers?”
, Philosophical Quarterly , 57(229): 513 – 534.
Grier, M. 2001. Kant’s Doctrine of
Transcendental Illusion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kreines, J. 2008a. “Hegel: Metaphysics
without Pre-Critical Monism.” Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great
Britain 57: 48–70.
Kreines, J. 2008b. “The Logic of Life:
Hegel’s Philosophical Defense of Teleological Explanation in
Biology.” In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth-Century
Philosophy, edited by F. Beiser, 344–77. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kreines, J. 2015. Reason in the World:
Hegel’s Metaphysics and its Philosophical Appeal. OUP.
Kreines, J. 2017.
“From Objectivity to the Absolute Idea in Hegel’s
Logic” in
The Oxford Handbook of Hegel. Ed. By Moyar.
Kreines, J. forthcoming. The Metaphysics of
Reason And Hegel’s Logic. Forthcoming in
Hegel-Studien.
Pippin. R. 1987. "Kant on the spontaneity of
mind', Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17, pp. 449- 76.
Pippin, R. 1989. Hegel’s Idealism. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Pippin. R. 1987. "Kant on the spontaneity of
mind', Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17, pp. 449- 76.
Proops, I. 2010. “Kant’s First Paralogism.”
Philosophical Review 119(4): 449–95.
Putnam, H., 1981, Reason, Truth, and History,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rorty, R. 1979. Philosophy and the mirror of
nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Rorty, R. 1995. 'Philosophy and the Future'
in H. Saatkamp (ed.), Rorty and Pragmatism: The Philosopher Responds
to His Critics, Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press.
Russell, B. 1927. The Analysis of Matter.
London: Kegan Paul.
I thank the
participants and audience at the conference, “Hegels
Philosophie als Metatheorie”.
I do not mean to
extend my complaint about Rorty’s reading of Hegel to
Kierkegaard himself. For I do not see reason to think that
Kierkegaard’s criticism requires the premise, which I
rejected above, that systematic philosophy is at heart
concerned with epistemological foundations. Kierkegaard may
have a very different worry about systematic philosophy, and
I think this topic is worth more consideration than I can
give it here.
I thank Axel Hutter
for questions and suggestions, especially on this topic.
See the pursuit of
this strategy in Pippin (2015).
Kreines 2012 and 2015
ch. 0.
E.g. Pippin 1989, 99,
148, 262#15, 280#15.
I interpret this
section in Kreines 2008b.
See Pippin 2015 on
metaphysics, including the topic of organic unity.
I argue this case in
more detail in Kreines 2008b.
One way to so
argue would be Pippin’s powerful argument (1987) that Kant’s
own epistemology pushes against Kant’s claim to metaphysical
neutrality, towards a robust metaphysics of the spontaneity
of the subject.
Here I follow Grier
2001, e.g. 2 and 144; Proops 2010, 455; and my 2015 chs. 0
and 4.
I thank Luca
Illetterati for helpful questions about the precise sense of
“metaphysics” here.
See the A-Preface
definition of metaphysics as conflict concerning questions
posed by our reason, which it cannot answer. Of course, Kant
also seeks to transform (Bxxii) metaphysics into a new form,
and to answer questions within this transformed metaphysics.
I follow here
my accounts in my 2008a and 2017.
SL
12:148/645. On chemism and “natural necessity” see SL
12:148/652.
I owe this
formulation to Bird (2007).
I follow here the
account in my (forthcoming).
From
Le Malade Imaginaire,
translation from Hutchison (1991).